Not even trying: the corruption of real science
Bruce G Charlton
University of Buckingham Press: Buckingham, UK.
2012
Note: This is a draft version of the book which
is substantively accurate but contains some typos and minor errors and a few
differences from the published paper/ Kindle version.
Note: The length is about 28,000 words, so
for ease of reading it may be best to copy and paste this text into a Word
document, edit and print it out.
Alternatively, the Kindle version is very
cheap...
***
Real science – a definition
Real Science noun
Science that operates on the basis of a belief in the reality of truth: that
truth is real.
Dedication
To the late John Ziman FRS (1925-2005) physicist, and great
understander of science; who wrote about Real Science in his book of that name,
and was probably the first to distinguish real science from what nowadays
calls-itself science but is not.
Note to the reader
This book might strike some people as bitter – it is not.
It is however viscerally and unapologetically angry –
although I hope to have kept this reasonably well under control...
The argument of this book in a single paragraph
Briefly, the argument of this book is that real science is dead,
and the main reason is that professional researchers are not even trying
to seek the truth and speak the truth; and the reason for this is that
professional ‘scientists’ no longer believe in the truth - no longer
believe that there is an eternal unchanging reality beyond human wishes and
organization which they have a duty to seek and proclaim to the best of their
(naturally limited) abilities. Hence the vast structures of personnel and
resources that constitute modern ‘science’ are not real science but instead
merely a professional research bureaucracy, thus fake or pseudo-science;
regulated by peer review (that is, committee opinion) rather than the
search-for and service-to reality. Among the consequences are that modern
publications in the research literature must be assumed to be worthless
or misleading and should always be ignored. In practice, this means that nearly
all ‘science’ needs to be demolished (or allowed to collapse) and real science carefully
rebuilt outside the professional research structure, from the ground up, by
real scientists who regard truth-seeking as an imperative and truthfulness as
an iron law.
Introduction
As a schoolboy and for many years afterwards, I was perhaps as idealistic
about science as anyone in recent years – it would not be much of an
exaggeration to say that I worshipped science; since I was an atheist
for whom science was the bottom-line description of reality. The great
scientists were my heroes – those whom I hoped to emulate.
For me nothing was more fundamental than science;
everything else was properly to be evaluated from the perspective of science.
Yet now I regard real science – the kind of science I used
to worship - as a thing of the past; an object of historical study. There are
small islands of real science dotted here and there, but with only local and
dwindling influence.
To all extents and purposes, I see real science as dead; and what
calls itself science is a fake – worse than nothing, because it claims so much:
claims indeed the noble mantle of real science.
*
This is not a matter of science having run-out of useful truths to
discover. It is that scientists are not any longer trying to discover useful
truths.
So, real science has essentially gone. What is now left – a vast,
international activity with millions of employed workers and multiple billions
of dollars of funding, is so thoroughly corrupt as to be un-reformable.
If enough people care enough about real science to want it back,
they will now have to build it all over again, from the ground up.
*
This book describes the essence of real science: a phenomenon much
simpler to describe – yet more difficult to do - than you might suspect.
It also charts the course of real science over about a thousand
years to its peak in the three centuries up to about 1950, then its
extraordinarily rapid – yet dishonestly concealed – collapse down to almost
nothing during the past two generations.
It is a remarkable story – covering some of the peaks of
accomplishment, and some of the darkest aspects of the human spirit.
Read on...
Understanding science retrospectively
The Owl of Minerva flies only at dusk said Hegel; implying that
understanding must be retrospective. Therefore we did not know what science
was, nor how it worked (in a philosophical, historical and sociological sense),
until real science was already well-advanced towards destruction.
For me, real science is the core of the modern world. Science is the creator
and driving force of genuine economic growth (increased efficiency in the
production, trade and distribution of essentials), and a significant driver of
social change; intellectually science is the crowning glory of modernity; but
at the same time and by the same mechanisms, science is responsible for most of
the distinctive horrors of the past couple of centuries.
*
My (very basic, to be amplified throughout this book) summary
understanding of the rise of real science was that it came from Pagan Greece
(epitomized by Aristotle), then through the early Christian theologians -
epitomized by the Western Medieval scholastic philosophers (pioneered by Peter
Abelard).
It was the Roman Catholic Church that professionalized philosophy
as a subject increasingly distinct from theology, and developed the university
as institutionally distinct from the monastery (thus dividing education from
devotion) – so, the Great Schism (when the Eastern Orthodox and Roman Catholic
Churches divided, around 1000 AD) marked the true beginning of modernity.
Then natural science separated from philosophy in the Renaissance
era, at around the time of Galileo, and later moved to be focused in Protestant
Northern Europe where it first became large, visible and noticeably distinct
from about the 17th century.
There were agrarian and industrial revolutions in Britain during the 1700s; and
from around 1800 a new world was increasingly apparent: a world characterized
by growth in science, technology, the economy, and human capability: the world
of modernity. And from this point science became not just a distinct social
structure, but a professional career structure.
*
Since the later 19th century, science has, with each
generation, broken-up into smaller and smaller specializations, and become more
and more career focused.
For a while this specialization led to greater achievement, since
it allowed the devotion of more time and effort to solving more manageable
problems. Yet each new-generation specialist had been educated in a more
generalist tradition – which acted as a drag on the tendency to fragmentation
and incoherence.
For a while, therefore, specialization led to greater accomplishment
within its individual divisions yet with sufficient integration across these
divisions to maintain unity and to check error.
However, specialization continued past this optimal point, and
into less-and-less functional fragmentation – such that science lost unity and
specialisms lost the ability to serve as mutual checks.
Science gradually became nothing but isolated and
irrefutable micro-specialisms.
Apparently, therefore, specialization was a slippery slope
for science: such that once science had stepped-onto the slippery slope of
specialization it could not stop the process, even when science
had slid far beyond the point at which specialization was helpful.
From real science to generic bureaucracy
At some point over the past several decades, science stopped being
real and evolved into its current state of being merely a research-based
variant of generic bureaucracy.
This was increasingly clear to aware observers from the 1960s, and
indeed to the most astute observers (such as Erwin Chargaff) from several
decades earlier. But now it is so obvious that only ignorance or dishonesty
prevents it being universally acknowledged.
However, bureaucracies are systematically ignorant, and dishonesty is now
institutional and compulsory, therefore the disappearance of real science is not
acknowledged but instead vehemently denied, and steady, incremental progress is
claimed!
*
Science presumably always was done among humans – albeit at a very
low prevalence; technological breakthroughs have tended to accumulate – albeit
with interruptions and local reversals - throughout recorded history; but
modernity happened because real scientific breakthroughs came so thick-and-fast
that increasing efficiency out-ran increasing population – and humanity escaped
what Gregory Clark has called the Malthusian Trap.
*
So far, the thesis is relatively uncontroversial. But if modernity
depends on the take-off of real science, upon what does the take-off of real
science depend?
My answer is creative genius.
My understanding is that real science grew fast – especially in
the populations of Northern Europe by recruiting from an increased pool of
‘creative geniuses’ who were motivated to do science. This I regard as the
essential underpinning of modernity.
*
The take-off of science therefore depended on two main things: 1.
a sufficient concentration of creative genius focused on scientific problems
plus 2. a modest degree of cognitive specialization.
That is to say, smart and creative people working cooperatively
on relatively-specific ‘scientific problems’.
And that, more or less, is my definition of science.
Merely that.
*
So, real science is smart and creative people working
cooperatively on scientific problems.
But science proved so useful that it became professionalized, and
initially this seemed to accelerate progress considerably. The first few
generations of professional scientists from the later 1800s into the twentieth
century were immensely productive of significant scientific breakthroughs.
Science seemed very obviously useful – the presumption was that
even-more science would be even-more useful...
And so the growth of professional science continued, and
continued...
Until it out-grew the supply of creative geniuses and had to
recruit from uncreative but very smart people - but continued growing...
Until it then out-grew the supply of uncreative but very smart
people, then it had to recruit from uncreative, only moderately smart but
hard-working people – but continued growing...
And so on and on, until ‘science’ consisted of whomsoever who
would do specific narrow technical and managerial jobs at the wage and
conditions on offer.
That’s where we are now...
*
More importantly, professional science initially recruited only
those who regarded the pursuit of truth as an iron law (and dishonesty
was punished by expulsion from science).
Yet, due to professionalization, science increasingly attracted careerists
rather than truth-seekers.
*
(Truth-seekers are typically resistant to bureaucratic
organization; and bureaucratic organization is intrinsically hostile to
truth-seekers.)
*
The professionalization of science having eliminated those who
were internally-motivated to seek truth; various formal mechanisms and procedures
were introduced to try and deal with purely careerist motivations. These mostly
amount to peer review mechanisms (peer review = the opinion of a group of
senior colleagues).
So, instead of truth-seeking, a filter of committee evaluations
was applied to ever-more-blatantly-careerist individual behaviour.
And science continued to grow - recruiting less- and
less-talented, weaker- and weaker-motivated, less- and less honest personnel until...
... until untalented, unmotivated and dishonest
career-orientated professional scientists became a large majority within
science and included most of the most successful researchers; thus
careerists took-over the peer review evaluation procedures such as to impose
their values; and ‘science’ became nothing but a ‘professional research
bureaucracy’.
I wasn’t actually doing science
Looking back on 25 years in professional research – I am forced to
admit that, although I certainly tried, I wasn’t actually doing science.
*
I began professional science in 1984 - or, at least, that's what I
thought I was doing.
Since then I worked in and across a variety of fields: neuro-endocrinology
(brain transmitters and blood hormones) in relation to psychiatry; the anatomy
and physiology of the adrenal gland (especially from 1989), epidemiology
(statistics of health and disease, from about 1991); evolutionary psychology
(evolutionary aspects of human behaviour including psychiatric illness and the
psycho-active drugs, from 1994); systems theory (understanding complex
biological organization, from about 2001); and from 2003-10 I edited an
international journal of ideas publishing work from the whole of medicine – and
sometimes beyond.
*
In all of these areas and some others I found serious problems
with the existing scientific literature: errors, inconsistencies, wrong framing
of problems.
(I don’t mean serious problems in-my-opinion; I mean that
problems objectively, undeniably serious to any honest, informed and competent
observer prepared to think for more than five consecutive minutes or two steps
of logic – whichever comes first.)
I was not shocked - after all, this is what science is supposedly
about, most of the time - providing the negative feedback to correct the wrong
stuff.
After all, science is not at any time-point supposed to be
wholly-correct, rather it is conceptualized as a system of intrinsic self-correction.
(Generating distinctive new lines of true and useful
scientific work is what we would all prefer to do, in other words to be original
- but only a few who are both very lucky and very able are able to achieve
this.)
*
My assumption was that - as the years rolled by - I would have the
satisfaction of seeing the wrong things tested, discredited, discarded and
replaced with more-correct knowledge. Error would be eliminated; truth
built-upon. So that overall, and in the long term, science would progress.
That is what was supposed to happen.
*
Well, it hasn't happened.
It hasn’t happened in any of the scientific fields with
which I am familiar or of which I have any knowledge. Indeed, instead, much
that was true and useful has been lost while much that is utterly worthless –
dishonest, incoherent, useless - has thriven.
A few decades ago one could assume that published work was honest
and competent (except in specific cases); now one must assume that published
work is dishonest and incompetent (except in specific cases).
A few decades ago one could assume that high status (“successful”)
scientists were honest and competent (except in specific cases); now one must
assume that famous and powerful scientists are dishonest and incompetent
(except in specific cases).
*
Overall it seems that things have gone backwards, and not
just slightly.
Yet research activity (personnel, funding, publishing,
communicating) have all increased exponentially – doubling in volume every 15
or so years (doubling every decade in medical research. And China has exploded
with research activity in the past 10 years).
So there has been massive expansion of inputs with first
stagnation then decline of outputs. Something has gone terribly wrong:
not just slightly wrong, but terribly wrong.
*
So, I must conclude that although I believed I was
participating in something called science, something that I thought I
understood from the writings of Jacob Bronowski and Karl Popper and from
reading the great genius scientists of the past – it turns-out that I wasn't
really doing science at all.
I was 'going through the motions' of doing science, true; but the machinery of
science was broken, and the work I was trying to do, and the work of those whom
I respected, was like a free-spinning-cog – disconnected from mainstream
activity.
If real science is that done from truth seeking motives and
communicated truthfully, then this kind of science had zero impact on the
mainstream.
Get this – real science had become detached from professional
research, technology and policy; and (most important) detached from practice:
detached from career success, status, funding, publication, prizes and
awards...
Real science had become a thing done for subjective personal
satisfaction merely a lifestyle choice – nobody else was interested.
*
Maybe real science was being done, maybe it was published, maybe
it was cited, maybe it was funded, maybe people made careers from doing it?
But in the end, real science did not make any difference:
real science had become just a private hobby.
Those few who were lucky enough to find a niche that supported
real science did so by accident, not by necessity; and the niches were
shrinking all the time.
And we who thought we were participating in the group
activity of real science were deluded – pleasantly deluded, perhaps; but
deluded.
If not real science, what are professional
‘scientists’ really doing?
The activity of mainstream modern Big Science is most reminiscent
of a Soviet Union era organization – such as the grossly unprofitable Polish
glass factory I saw on TV being inspected by John Harvey Jones in his TV show Troubleshooter.
The factory was producing vast quantities of defective drinking
glasses which nobody wanted. Nobody wanted to buy them nor even to use
them. So the glasses were simply piling-up in gigantic stacks around the
factory building – using-up resources, getting in everybody’s way, and
taking-up all the useful space.
When Harvey Jones was asked what to do, how to make the business profitable, he
said the first essential step was stop making the glasses.
*
Stop now: this very minute, he said. Go out of this office
and switch-off the production line, send all the factory workers home (on full
pay) for a few weeks, and begin sorting it out.
But so long as the workers were attending daily, beavering-away, filling-in
paperwork, with raw materials pouring-in on thundering lorries; the masses of
defective glasses were being churned-out, stacked until they were blocking the
aisles and preventing anything useful being done... there was no hope.
Better to pay people for doing nothing than this!
*
Same with professional science – stop it now, for goodness
sake!
Switch-off the assembly line - please!
Stop wasting vast human and physical resources in piling-up
useless stuff that nobody wants. Better to pay researchers to do nothing
than this...
*
(Obviously it would be better if people did something useful than
nothing – so maybe ex-professional researchers could be dressed warmly and paid
to lie across the threshold of closed doors to function as draught-excluders?)
*
So, here we have the problem of professional science today – it
has been bloated by decades of exponential growth into a
bureaucratically-dominated heavy industry Soviet factory, characterized by
vastly inefficient mass production of shoddy goods that nobody wants.
And professional science is trundling along,
hour by hour, day by day; masses of people going to work, doing things, saying
things, writing things, getting funding, spending money, advertising
themselves, engaging in petty gossip, intrigues and back-stabbing…
Science is hopelessly and utterly un-reformable while it continues to be so
big, continues to grow-and-grow, and continues uselessly to churn out ever-more
of its sub-standard and unwanted goods.
Switch it off: stop making the defective glasses: now...
The pervasive dishonesty
of modern ‘science’
How did we get from useful and real science to useless research
bureaucracies generating hype and spin for the public relations industry?
Anyone who has been a scientist for more than 20 years will
realize that there has been a progressive, significant and indeed qualitative
decline in the honesty of communications between scientists, between scientists
and their employing institutions, and between scientists and their institutions
and the outside world.
In a nutshell – science has gone from being basically honest to basically
dishonest (and in the process gone from being real science to professional
research).
*
Naturally enough, the pervasive atmosphere of dishonesty has long
since led to scientists being dishonest with themselves - and once this
happened the situation of endemic corruption itself became wholly deniable.
(The primary and fundamental act of scientific dishonesty is: denial
of the pervasive reality of scientific dishonesty.)
The situation now is that what calls itself scientific research is
essentially dishonest, not incidentally so; such that honest (real)
science is on the one hand very rare and on the other hand it has negligible
impact on the conduct of mainstream research.
(From my experience it seems that real science is nowadays more
likely to be actively-suppressed, and real scientists systematically
persecuted, than for either to be encouraged.)
*
More exactly, mainstream research is not so much dishonest as non-honest:
it is simply unconcerned by matters such as seeking truth and rigid
truthfulness in its discourse. Mainstream research is not about truth –
it is doing other things.
*
So of course modern ‘science’ is dishonest – why on earth
should it be honest when it is not even trying to be honest? Research is
not being done to find the truth, experiments are not done to test the truth,
scientific ideas and results are not written-up in order to communicate the
truth.
Truth doesn’t go into it. Why on earth, then, should anybody
imagine that truth will come out of it?
Mainstream professional research is no more about honesty than
advertising, politics or official statistics are about honesty.
Which is to say that in modern professional research there is just
enough narrowly-factual accuracy to render deniable its basic and
motivated dishonesty.
*
Yet real science must be an arena where truth is the rule;
or else the activity simply stops being science and becomes something else –
professional research, a job, a bureaucratic institution, an arbitrary activity
done to justify funding.
The honesty of real science is not merely a desirable
feature, an optional extra, it is intrinsic to the activity – real science is
built-around honesty as its core ethic.
Discard honesty and there is nothing left of science.
*
Mathematicians know that even random (accidental, undirected)
errors multiply very rapidly – third and fourth generation analogue recording
are more crackle than music and beyond that there is just crackle. Yet random
errors occur equally in both directions from the signal, noise tends to cancel
out; and so can be averaged. The signal can be retrieved from even a great deal
of noise.
But systematic error cannot be averaged, because there is
no reason to assume that falsity is equally distributed on either side of the
truth: and dishonesty is a systematic error.
Truth cannot be retrieved from a mass of lies – so without strict honesty, truth is simply lost...
Communications within the science profession
The most egregious domain of untruthfulness is probably where scientists
speak or write about their own work.
When modern researchers are preparing applications for funding,
there is clearly no notion that they should be trying to communicate the truth.
The idea would be regarded as ridiculous! The whole motive and rationale of the
exercise is to write a successful application: in other words to get
yourself money by selling (what you claim are) your research results and plans.
The veracity of what is being claimed is merely a means
to an end. The funder neither expects truth nor does the applicant expect
to write truth – grantsmanship is thus a kind of game (albeit with high
stakes) where one side sets up the rules, and the other side tries to be as
dishonest as it can get away with, while sticking to the letter of the rules -
then the first side tries to catch them out in an inconsistency.
Modern research grant proposals therefore resemble the official accounts
of organized crime – everyone knows that they are intentionally and carefully
faked, but the auditors are allowed only to check for internal consistency
among the lies. Consistent lying is fine – indeed admired and rewarded.
So long as the information in grant proposals and research
publications has been thoroughly laundered, then everybody is happy
(well, ‘everybody’ who has influence over career success – and for modern
researchers that is everybody-who-matters...).
*
When a modern researcher describes the nature and significance of
his research to another researcher in the same field, for example in a writing
a publication or speaking at a conference or in the casual interactions of
scientific life; or to a bureaucrat or official who might directly or
indirectly influence his pay and conditions (say a university administrator);
or to a journalist or media person, or even to a random member of the public –
there is no notion of the modern researcher trying to be truthful about the
nature and significance of his research.
Trying strictly to be truthful would indeed be regarded as
evidence of naiveté, or – if persisted-with - actively dangerous.
Modern research communication is strategic – it is a means
to an end: and the degree of veracity of what is being said is controlled
by the requirements of that end.
Dishonesty as pervasive, endemic
Once they have been observed, selected and trained; real
scientists are unreflectingly honest and will trust each other; but their
honesty is also enforced by a multitude of informal processes – if, after being
trusted, that trust is betrayed there is the permanent sanction of
exclusion from real science. From that point, real scientists will simply
ignore you.
*
In discussing the dishonesty of modern ‘science’ it is tempting to
focus on cases of ‘fraud’ – especially instances in which specific researchers
have fabricated, invented or deliberately distorted their results for personal
gain.
It is tempting but misleading, because it assumes honesty as a
baseline. While real scientists are indeed habitually truthful, modern
professional researchers by contrast are not even trying to be truthful.
Truth is a positive value. However, at most, modern researchers
are trying not to be factually incorrect – which is as different
from trying to be truthful as a scandal-mongering tabloid ‘investigative’
journalist is different from Einstein.
This is not a subtle matter. Nor is it a matter for debate. It is
absolutely plain and obvious on a day-by-day level in the conduct and
conversation of modern researchers. Compared with real scientists, the mass
of modern researchers (including, perhaps especially, scientific leaders) are
neither motivated nor regulated by truth, nor do they speak about truth, nor do
they discriminate on the basis of truthfulness.
*
You doubt this?
Just watch! Just listen! Just read! So long as you can tell the difference between
on the one hand someone trying to be as truthful as they can be, and on the
other hand someone trying to sell something – then it is a
no-brainer.
Dishonesty with oneself
So pervasive are the petty misrepresentations and cautious lies, it
is evidence that many scientists are now dishonest even with themselves, in the
privacy of their own thoughts.
Such things can happen to initially honest people either by force
of habit, or because they never knew any better (never having met,
leave-aside worked-with, a real scientist); and because lies breed lies
in order to explain the discrepancies between predictions and observations,
between claims and outcomes.
*
Lying to oneself may be one cause of the remarkable incoherence of
so much modern scientific thinking, when coherence is evaluated across the
whole range of human knowledge.
(The coherence of modern science is restricted to the
micro-specialty; where it is the artificial result of laundering rather than
natural consequence of honestly reporting perceived reality.)
It is much easier to be coherent, and to recognize incoherence,
when discourse is uncontaminated by deliberate misrepresentations. There is
less to cover-up.
Most people can think-straight only by being completely honest
with themselves and with everybody else. Maybe straight thinking doesn’t matter
in some areas of life – but science is about straight thinking or it is
nothing.
If scientists are not honest even with themselves, then their work
will be a mess – or rather, because modern researchers are not honest
with themselves their work is a mess.
*
Scientists are usually too cautious and timid to risk telling
outright lies about important things, or to invent and emphasize fake data;
but instead they push the envelope of exaggeration, selectivity and distortion
as far as possible. And tolerance for this kind of untruthfulness has greatly
increased over recent years.
So it is now routine, normal, indeed required behaviour for
scientists deliberately to exaggerate, to ‘hype’ the significance of their
status and performance, and ‘spin’ the importance of their research.
The envelope of exaggeration is now extended to the
not-impossible: so if it is in reality not-impossible that my research might
(under highly implausible but not-impossible combinations of conditions)
assist in some way in curing cancer... then it is nowadays permissible (in a
‘good’ cause – i.e. when it is expedient) to present the research as being progress
towards curing cancer.
In sum, when a modern researcher says ‘my research is progress
towards curing cancer’ it really means ‘it is not impossible that my
research could conceivably count as progress towards curing cancer’.
*
Furthermore, it is entirely normal and unremarkable for ordinary
‘scientists’ to spend their entire professional life doing work they know in
their hearts to be trivial or bogus – preferring that which promotes their
career over that which has the best chance of advancing science.
Indeed, it is entirely normal and unremarkable for the best
modern ‘scientists’ to spend their entire professional life doing sub-optimal
work they know in their hearts to be less scientifically ambitious than they
are capable of.
In a nutshell the most successful modern researchers have replaced
scientific ambition with career ambition.
Far from being frowned-upon, such gross and treacherous
misapplication of research effort is positively encouraged, nay
enforced, and not just sometimes but as the norm in many places and by many
people, including what are supposed to be the best places for research
(universities and other institutions); because careerism is a more reliable
route to high productivity than real science.
In fact it may be impossible to get a job, or get tenure, or
promotion - except by dumping idealism and scientific ambition and embracing
low-risk careerism.
*
Indeed, senior scientists in the best places are clever,
hard-working and intelligent enough rapidly to become expert at hyping mundane
research to create a misleading impression of revolutionary importance. Far
from resisting, or fighting, the degradation of science; the senior researchers
at the ‘best’ places have led (indeed driven) their subordinates into
a morass of corruption, like so many demonically-possessed Gadarene swine.
It is a kind of Gresham’s Law at work; when dishonest research is
treated as if it were real science; then bad research drives out the good.
*
So, in real science there is, there must be, zero-tolerance
for dishonesty and zero-compromise with truthfulness.
Truth-telling and truth-seeking must not be regarded as mere
ideals within science, but as iron laws, continually and universally
operative.
Causes of dishonesty in science
Although some scientists are selfishly dishonest simply in order
to promote their own careers, for most people quasi-altruistic arguments for
lying (dishonesty in a good cause of helping others, or to be an agreeable
colleague) are likely to be a more powerful inducement to routine
untruthfulness than is the gaining of personal advantage.
For example, scientists are strongly pressured to be
less-than-wholly-truthful for the benefit of their colleagues or institutions,
or for official/political reasons – for example in fund-raising, or complying
with inspections or external research evaluations.
(And in areas of science that impinge on the taboos of political
correctness or the imperatives of ‘progressive’ politics, honesty is punishable
with extreme disincentives – career termination, media-orchestrated
vilification, legal prosecution, threatened and actual violence.)
*
Often, scientists are unable (without attracting severe sanctions)
to opt-out of administrative or managerial exercises which all-but insist-upon
dishonest responses – and for which colleagues expect dishonesty in
order to promote the interests of the group.
Failure to comply would be seen as selfish scrupulousness at the
expense of colleagues. There would be no support from scientific leaders –
whose careers stand to benefit most from success in administrative or
managerial exercises.
Project leaders may feel responsible for raising money to support the
livelihood of their junior team members; and feel obliged to do whatever type
of research is most generously funded, and to say or write whatever is
necessary to obtain that funding.
Failure to do whatever it takes to secure funding or
survival in a bureaucratic system would be seen as a failure to provide for
your dependents – as sacrificing peoples livelihoods on the altar of your own smug
desire to feel virtuous...
*
So, in a bureaucratic context where cautious and consistent
dishonesty is rewarded, strict truthfulness is taboo and will cause
trouble for colleagues, for teams, for whole institutions.
Because when everyone else is exaggerating their
achievement then any precisely accurate person will be judged as even
worse than their already modest claims.
If every fourth rate scientist is claiming to be third rate
– but after inflation-adjustment is judged to be fourth rate; then
honestly to label oneself as fourth rate would lead to being to be judged as
fifth rate - on the assumption that you, like everyone else, must be indulging
in hype.
In this kind of situation, individual truthfulness will be
interpreted either as simply stupid, or as an irresponsible indulgence.
*
Clearly then, even in the absence of the sort of direct coercion
which prevails in many un-free societies, scientists may be subjected to such
pressure that they are more-or-less forced to be dishonest; and this
situation can (in decent people) lead to feelings of regret, or to shame and
remorse.
The only alternative is some species of martyrdom.
*
This is a situation which leads decent people to feel shame and
remorse.
Unfortunately, shame may not lead to remorse but instead to rationalization,
to self-exculpation, to the elaborate construction of excuses - and eventually
a denial of dishonesty. In other words, shame may lead to aggressive
hypocrisy.
But eventually the situation leads many to cynicism; hypocrisy is
abandoned as ludicrously implausible – and there is a cynical advocacy
of dishonesty. Such cynics feel they are merely being honest in advocating open
dishonesty, because everyone is doing this anyway. Better – they think – to be
a cynic advocating evil than a hypocrite pretending to good.
Yet, whatever are the motivations and reasons
for research dishonesty, it has been by such means that modern ‘scientists’
have become inculcated into habitual falsity; until people have become
used-to dishonesty, don’t notice dishonesty, eventually come to expect and
finally insist-upon dishonesty.
Roots of dishonesty in science – the role of
peer review
My belief is that science has rotted from the head down –
from the top to the bottom - and therefore blame mostly lies with senior
‘scientists’.
The careerism of senior ‘scientists’, and their abandonment of the
Iron Law of truthfulness, has been the main cause of the now pervasive
corruption of science (not least because the senior appoint the junior, the
bosses choose the minions).
So the roots of dishonesty in science constitute a ‘treason of the
clerks’ phenomenon.
*
While the ultimate cause of the treason has been the abandonment
of truth conceived as a transcendental value – as I argue below – the
proximate mechanism by which corruption has been implemented was peer review.
Since the middle twentieth century there has been a massive
expansion and not influence of peer review, peer review infiltrated into all
the major scientific evaluations – peer review has become the self-perceived
core process of science.
Yet peer review is no more, no less, than the opinion of
senior scientists. And individual judgment, but a procedure for gathering
opinions of a group, followed by some kind of more-or-less formal,
more-or-less explicit procedure for deriving a single decision from the group
of opinions: by vote, by veto, by some kind of weighted quantification, by an
impressionistic judgment of the decision, or whatever.
In practice, most peer review is a ‘black box’ mechanism – and all
the more effective for its unknown operations. A question is fed-into the black
box of peer review, some senior scientists deliberate in some way and some
answer emerges – an answer that is impossible to critique yet regarded as
authoritative (as if a committee of senior scientists constituted a kind
of super-hero-scientist with magically-combined wisdom and expertise!)
The essence of peer review is therefore the ‘peers’ – which implicitly
means a plurality of senior figures from (broadly) the same domain or field of
research endeavour; and the ‘review’ element which in some way derives a
bimodal or categorical evaluation from the plurality of opinions.
*
To put it another way, the triumph of peer review is a triumph of
the committee over the individual, of procedure over judgment, of the selective
and explicit over the unbounded and implicit.
The even-more-significant aspect of peer review is the rhetorical
success of implying that a committee procedure is more objective and more valid
than individual judgment; the almost-wholly successful trick of disguising that
peer review is pure opinion, and therefore just as ‘unreliable’ and prone to
corruption as individual judgment – but that in fact peer review is worse than
individual judgment for the same reason that a committee decision is
intrinsically worse than an individual decision: because the committee decision
is removed from individual responsibility, hence removed from responsibility
altogether.
(Responsibility is an attribute of individual authority. Without
I.A. there is no responsibility – merely a legal contract.)
Yet peer review is neither necessary nor sufficient as a
definition of science, it is orthogonal to science; and therefore
domination by peer review marks the disappearance of ‘real science’ and the
inclusion of its activities within the system of large, complex trans-national
bureaucracies.
*
So peer review does not solve the problem of subjectivity;
rather it replaces potentially responsible individual subjectivity with
necessarily irresponsible group subjectivity.
Thus the advantage of peer review is precisely the opposite of its
propaganda – peer review has become universal because it is irresponsible,
not despite this.
For peer review; irresponsibility is a feature, not a bug.
*
Overall, senior scientists have set a bad example of
untruthfulness, self-seeking and lack of principle in their own
behaviour, and (surely not unrelated) they have also tended to administer
science in such a way as to reward hype and careful-dishonesty, and punish
modesty and strict truth-telling.
Some senior scientists have laudably refused to compromise their
honesty, however they have done this largely by quietly ‘opting-out’, and not
much by using their power and influence to create and advertise alternative
processes and systems in which honest scientists might work. They have not exposed
the pervasive and mandatory dishonesty of modern ‘science.
Presumably they began by not wanting to discredit what real
science still remained, but ended by colluding in the disguise of the
non-scientific nature of pseudo-scientific professional research.
But, to be fair to the honest real scientists, those that did
speak out loudly and clearly – such as Erwin Chargaff - were first
marginalized, then ridiculed, then completely ignored and forgotten – as being
embittered failures, motivated by ‘sour grapes’ and envy...
*
Peer review - of ever greater complexity, hence irresponsibility -
has now been applied everywhere: to academic education and research training,
job appointments and promotions, to scientific publications and conferences, to
ethical review, to research funding, to the allocation of medals, prizes and
awards.
And peer review processes are set-up and manned by senior
scientists. In a sense, peer review (where it matters, where it makes a
difference to policy and practice) simply is monopolization of all
evaluation, reward or punishment processes by senior scientists; yet not as
autonomous individuals but as components of a process which
nobody-in-particular controls.
This seems something like the worst of all
possible worlds; most of the actual disadvantages of tyranny but without any of
the potential advantages of having ‘somebody’ in control.
Modern ‘science’ is de facto dishonest
Of course not every single modern scientist is dishonest, and not
every last branch of professional science is corrupt.
However, in practice, they might as well be.
By ‘in practice’ I mean to make that distinction that, from the
transcendental and ultimate perspective, corruption is an evil and thus every
individual science who holds out against the prevailing dishonesty counts.
Yet when honest scientists and truthful specialties are disarticulated
from the processes of mainstream science (especially from the outputs of peer
review processes) then these do not affect functioning of the system.
The existence of a few honest souls does not refute the charge of
general scientific dishonesty – just as the existence of a handful of impartial
judges does not refute the charge of systemic legal corruption.
(After all the rare honest judge can be, often is, over-ruled by
corrupt superiors. It happens.)
Peer review is neither a necessary nor
sufficient part of real science
I have often read comments which state explicitly, or assume
implicitly, that peer review is what sets science apart from other (less valid)
modes of knowledge.
Yet this is simply, observably, demonstrably false. Peer review is
neither necessary nor sufficient to real science.
Peer review is not necessary, nor was peer review a feature
of science in its golden age, when science worked best – most effectively and
efficiently.
Old writings never mention anything like modern peer review. In
those eras decision making was mostly, sometimes wholly, individual and
personal (with certain exceptions where a ‘collegial’ method of decision
making was used to allocate goods that were generated and controlled by an
institution).
And peer review is not distinctive to science, but
is indeed (very obviously – I would have thought) found in all academic
subjects nowadays; and is characteristic of many formal bureaucracies. Indeed,
peer review is perhaps the defining feature, the hallmark of modern
bureaucracies in which personal responsibility has been replaced by
(deliberately, not accidentally) unaccountable committee procedures.
*
The over-expansion and domination of peer review in science is
therefore a sign of scientific decline and decadence, not (as so commonly
asserted) a sign of increased rigour.
Peer review as the ultimate arbiter represents the conversion of
real science to generic bureaucracy; a replacement of testing knowledge by
opinions about knowledge; a replacement of objectivity by subjectivity –
imposing a procedural but arbitrary subjectivity rather than having individual
subjectivity linked to responsibility.
And the increased role for de facto irresponsibility in
science has created space into which dishonesty has expanded.
When modern ‘science’ is not honest, as it typically is not, then
peer review ensures that nobody-in-particular is identifiably
to-blame for the situation.
*
As well as from the careerism of senior scientists, inducements to
dishonesty have also come from outside of science – from politics, government
administration and the media (for example), all of whom are continually
attempting to distort science to their own agenda and covert real science to
the service of their power.
At present, the situation in the UK is that a researcher cannot
get money from a government source without perjuring themselves.
(Naturally, I refer to perjury by appropriately scientific
criteria of departure from absolute truth-full-ness; and not by
irrelevant legal criteria of perjury as provable-lying.)
(The skill of scientific perjury, as practiced by the most modern
successful researchers, is indeed precisely to commit scientific perjury while
avoiding legal perjury.)
*
But whatever the origin of the pressures to corrupt science, it is
obvious that the scientific leadership have themselves been corrupted and
co-opted.
The alternative would have been inflexible resistance on a matter
of principle – the principle of truth-seeking and truth-speaking as an Iron Law
intrinsic to science, even to the point of ‘martyrdom’.
Notable individuals from past generations of scientists did indeed
stand up for their beliefs to the extent of being sacked, imprisoned, exiled or
even killed. We moderns can only stand in awe of such principled behaviour.
But modern ‘scientists’ have been kept in-line
without any need for recourse to such draconian measures. The mildest of
implied threats have been enough to convert real scientists into careerist
drones.
In real science truth must be a transcendental
value
Why, how did past generations of real scientist behave so much better –
so much more truthfully - than modern professional researchers?
I have come to believe that real science depends for its long-term
success on an explicit and pervasive pursuit of the ideal of transcendental
truth.
‘Transcendental’ implies that a value is outside the material world; is real,
stable and ultimate – it is aimed-at but can only imperfectly and imprecisely
be known, achieved or measured.
So, transcendental truth is an ideal but actual thing, located
outside of science; beyond and above scientific methods, processes and peer
consensus.
*
Transcendental truth is not, therefore, evaluated by
science; but is instead the proper aim of real science. It is regulatory
of real science.
(Technically, transcendental truth is a metaphysical assumption.
And that-there-is-no-such-thing-as-transcendental-truth is also a metaphysical
assumption.)
Especially truth is the proper aim of scientists as individuals.
In other words, science should be a social system constituted by individual
scientists who are dedicated truth-seekers: whose practice of science includes
‘truth talk’ that references current actuality to ideal aspirations and who
practice ‘the habit of truth’.
Real science is not, therefore, made of institutions, nor
organizations, nor of rules, methods nor processes – real science is made by,
done by, individuals: people working together to discover and communicate
reality.
Jacob Bronowski on the habit of truth
Jacob Bronowski (1908-1974) invented the term 'the habit of truth'
to describe the fundamental and distinctive ethic of science: the main
foundation upon which was built the success of science, providing the means
(knowledge) for mankind to shape the natural world.
Bronowski emphasized this, since it was (and is) often imagined that science is
a morally neutral activity. This is wrong. Because, although scientific
knowledge is indeed morally neutral (and can be used for good or evil), the practice
of science (including being a scientist) is certainly a moral activity - based
on the habit of truth.
He argued that for science to be truthful as a whole it is not sufficient to
aim at truth as an ultimate outcome, scientists must also be habitually
truthful in the ‘minute particulars’ of their scientific lives.
The end does not justify the means, instead Bronowski
argued that the means are indivisible from the end: scientific work is ‘of a
piece, in the large and in detail; so that if we silence one scruple about our
means, we infect ourselves and our ends together’.
*
Bronowski’s insight was that – to be successful in terms of the
test of shaping the natural world, each and every scientist in his scientific
communications must speak the truth as he understands it.
To put it another way – scientists must be trying to seek
the truth, trying to be truthful – all the time and about everything.
Indeed, I think it likely that the social structure of science is
at root nothing more than a group of people investigating reality who
seek truth and speak truth habitually (and if, or when, they cannot be
truthful, they will either state this or say nothing).
*
Bronowski perceived that societies which abandoned, indeed
persecuted, the habit of truth – such as, in his time, the USSR and Nazi
Germany – paid the price in terms of losing their ability to perceive or
generate the underlying knowledge of reality which forms the basis of shaping
the natural world.
(Note – these were societies which had had the habit of truth in
science at one time, but then ‘lost’ it; or rather – like ourselves – actively crushed
it.)
This declining ability to shape the natural world was concealed with
propaganda, but such concealment could only be temporary since the cause of the
decline was strengthened by every attempt to deny it.
But, the scientific failures of Germany, and especially the USSR,
were obvious in comparison with the USA and the UK – however, when the USA and
the UK abandoned truth (along with pretty much all other places) then there was
no comparator; the effect was not obvious, could more easily be hidden...
(After all, somebody will be awarded a Nobel Prize every
year – whether or not anybody deserves it, whether or not there is any real
science being done in the field in question.)
*
Having grown up strongly under the influence of Bronowski (for
good and for ill) and also this distinctive morality of science, I have witnessed
at first hand the rapid loss of the habit of truth from science.
At first I saw an encapsulated
loss whereby scientists continued to be truthful with each other (that is,
truthful in the sense of speaking the truth as they see it) while lying to outsiders
(especially in order to get grants, promote their research, and to deflect
criticism)...
Then scientists stopped
being truthful with other scientists (who were now seen as competitors,
gatekeepers, potential patrons)...
After which the
situation degenerating swiftly to the final surrender whereby scientists are no
longer truthful even with themselves.
*
At the same time I have seen hype (i.e. propaganda) expand from being
merely a superficial sheen added to real science in order to make it more
interesting to the general public, to the present situation where hype defines
reality for scientists (as well as everyone else) – where propaganda is so
pervasive that nobody can know what – maybe nothing at all, or the opposite to
the propaganda – lies beneath it.
There is, indeed, no ‘beneath’ since by now hype goes all the way
through science: from top to bottom, inside and out.
A 50 year experiment in excluding
transcendental truth from scientific discourse
Although the ultimate scientific authority of a transcendental
value of truth (located outside of current scientific practice) was a view
almost universally held by the greatest scientists throughout recorded history,
and was a frequent topic of discourse among scientists and in the literature
until the mid-20th century; modern science has pretty much dispensed with the
idea of truth.
References to truth in an ultimate sense have by now been all-but
banished from professional scientific literature and discourse; being regarded
by a younger generation of hard-nosed and technically-orientated researchers as
wishful, mystical and embarrassing at best – and hypocritical or manipulative
at worst.
Instead, all disputes are constrained to operate within an
evaluation system of proximate methodology and peer approved standard practice.
*
Such exclusion of references to truth from scientific discourse
could be regarded as an experiment which has been gathering support for
about 50 years – although the overlapping of scientific generations meant that
senior scientists continued to discuss truth in a transcendental fashion at
least into the 1980s, and a handful still continue.
The experiment in exclusion of truth talk was driven (presumably)
partly by the desire for greater efficiency (the desire for less
metaphysical chit-chat and more hard science) – and partly on the belief
that transcendental values serve no practical function – merely waste
time and energy, confuse and mislead. The assumption was that science could
more-efficiently be done using just internal, professional (within-science)
evaluations.
Partly it was also driven by the increasing prevalence of
materialist atheism – such that ‘scientists’ no longer believe in transcendental
reality; indeed some modern ‘scientists’ seem not to believe that there
is any reality separate from social structures that describe and define
what-counts-as-truth. They seem to operate on the basis that reality is
‘socially constructed’.
Modern ‘scientists’ are not interested in whether something really
is true; they are interested only in whether peer review says it
is true – they are interested only in whether something is fashionable, funded,
publishable in high-impact fora, and likely to attract jobs, promotions and
prizes.
Even those who publicly oppose and ridicule the idea of social
construction of ‘reality’ behave as if a vote from a peer review
committee of senior ‘scientists’ is the nearest possible approximation to truth
– which is a view as close to pure reality-denying nihilism as makes no
difference...
*
This profound shift within science was described tellingly in Real
Science by the late John Ziman (1925-2005) (from whom I took the sub-title
of this book). Ziman was a British physicist of great distinction as well as a
philosopher and sociologist of science, and on the advisory board of Medical
Hypotheses when I was editor.
Ziman termed the transformation in science during his lifetime a
change from ‘academic science’ to ‘post-academic science’.
Academic science is what I call ‘real’ science; post-academic
science is what I call ‘professional research’.
*
In Ziman’s description, post-academic’ discourse is
implicitly framed such that questions of truth have lost their meaning. It is a
type of Big Science – focused on the organization and funding of projects.
Real Science
memorably describes the transformation in the fine texture of a successful
scientist’s life, the day to day activities.
The old style ‘academic’ or real scientist does science –
tries to discover, theorise and describe the truth about reality.
But the typical day of a modern, professional-researching
post-academic ‘scientist’ is non-overlappingly distinct from this. It is, in
essence, the life of a bureaucrat, of a manager – combining personnel
administration and project organizing with public relations, arranging for
publication, fund-raising, publicity and presentations.
*
The lack of any anchor from research practice to transcendental
truth has rendered many areas of modern ‘science’ a kind of ‘glass bead game’
(to use the term from Herman Hesse’s novel), comprising research disciplines
that are free-spinning cogs with little or no explanatory, predictive or
manipulative connection with the natural world.
By its ultimate reliance on professional evaluations (various
different versions of peer review applied to research funding, publication,
prizes, promotions, etc.) modern ‘science’ has become structurally
indistinguishable from academic literary criticism: both being arcane,
technically non-intuitive and rigorous, sometimes intellectually brilliant –
but ultimately internally-validated fashion-driven high brow pastimes
comprised of ringing variations for the sake of career advancement.
The experiment in trying to do science without reference to transcendental
truth has therefore failed utterly. In discarding transcendental truth, science
discarded what had made it science.
What is left over is a fundamentally dishonest sham which
tries to claim the distinctive validity of real science without submitting to
the iron discipline of truth.
But is truth really true, or was it just
a convenient fiction?
It seems that transcendental truth is needed in science, for
science to work, for science to remain science.
Only when science is truth-seeking can its practice mobilize the most profound
dedication from its practitioners – a level of motivation far greater than that
elicited by peer-approval-seeking science, or science done from a familial or
social sense of duty.
Recall; when scientists believed in truth they would historically
suffer hardship (sometimes extreme hardship, prison, even death) for their
scientific beliefs. But nowadays even the mere possibility of being passed over
for a grant or promotion is sufficient to terrify ‘scientists’ into submission.
Another reason for valuing truth is the need for science as a
social system to tolerate (and if possible actively support) individuals who
seek truth – even when this generates greater risk and a short term reduction
in performance.
Likewise the discipline of transcendental truth enables science to
tolerate the fact that many brilliant and creative scientists will often have
unworldly, erratic or abrasive personalities.
In other words, only the living presence of truth in the
daily practice of science may provide a higher context for decision-making in
which considerations of social expediency can potentially be transcended.
*
But despite these advantages, the ‘big question’ for any modern
scientist is whether transcendental truth really is ‘true’ or is merely a
convenient fiction.
By ‘convenient fiction’ I mean the idea that even if it could
convincingly be argued that scientists work better when they believe in
transcendental truth; such ’truth’ is actually no more than a delusion,
albeit a useful delusion.
The convenient fiction argument is that in reality there is no
such thing as truth but it is a good thing for science and for society when
scientists act as if truth is real.
*
The discussion then moves beyond science, and to the
presuppositions of science; moves to a level of the basic understanding of
things – in other words, to metaphysics.
Early scientists generally assumed (I mean they assumed at a metaphysical
level – as their conception of the nature of reality) that the truth was
reality - a property of the universe created by a god.
Truth (knowledge of reality) was communicated in outline to humans
partly by being in-built (by god) as human nature and partly from divine revelation;
truth was understood by means of reason (which was valid because also
god-given), and applied to the study of Nature by god-given human ingenuity.
Early scientists therefore believed in both god/s and truth.
Later scientists (from the late 19th century into the
early 20th century) were atheists about god but realists about
truth. For example Albert Einstein had an abstract, or pantheistic view of an
ordered universe and a belief in the fortunate (but not god-given) rational and
intuitive ability of humans to understand the nature of reality.
*
Most of these scientists of several generations ago were theists,
more or less; believing in an impersonal god who created order (and the order
was real – for example mathematics or the laws of physics were real); but
setting-aside divine aspects of individual salvation, meaning and purpose.
Another generation or two onwards, and most of the best scientists
were atheists about god and also did not believe in the reality of truth. They
disbelieved in both God and truth, nonetheless the best scientists continued to
behave as if they did regard truth as real. For example Richard Feynman
was not religious and seemingly did not believe in transcendental truth
but anyway lived and worked by a strict personal ethic of truthfulness
and truth-seeking.
Modern scientists have abandoned all this as so much useless
baggage. They are atheists about god, relativists about truth, and careerists
in their behaviour: they neither believe, nor behave as if they believe, in transcendental
truth.
*
So, the historical sequence was: theism, deism, atheism.
Deism perhaps enabled the greatest science; but deism was
temporary and en route between theism and atheism.
How a scientist behaves is clearly more important than his or her
belief system. Einstein and Feynman behaved (with respect to science) in an
exemplary fashion.
Yet viewed through the ‘retrospectoscope’ I am not convinced of
the coherence or long-term sustainability of Feynman’s views – nor even
Einstein’s.
To be truthful yet believing neither in transcendental truth nor
in a personal relationship with deity, now just looks like another unstable phase
between theism and atheism – a perspective restricted to the transitional
generation of people who were brought-up religiously then abandoned it in
adulthood.
The next generation, their children and grand-children – born from
the mid-twentieth century onwards, were brought-up as secular materialists,
have moved decisively to atheism and also to non-truthfulness.
*
In a nutshell, it seems that there are several ways to live by
transcendental truth – ranging from formal religion to a pragmatic assumption
that it is expedient to act as-if truth were real.
But some belief systems relating to truth are more stable and
coherent than others, and some belief systems are more powerfully motivating
than others.
For scientists, the crucial matter is that each real scientist
must, must, must (for whatever reason) work according to a binding
personal ethic of the importance and reality of transcendental truth – that
truth lies beyond and above science; and science must be practiced according to
this reality
Not even trying...
While wanting to know the truth does not mean that you will
find the truth; on the other hand, if scientists are not even trying to
discover the truth - then the truth certainly will not be discovered.
Even if stumbled-upon, or tripped-over by happy accident by
someone not looking for it, then truth will fail to be recognized
as true.
If the truth is in a particular direction, then there are many
more directions (an infinite number of them) where the truth cannot be
found; so when a researcher is not looking for the truth, the chances of
finding it are one to infinity.
In a nutshell, there are an infinite number of ways to be wrong,
but only one way to be right.
(Of course, nobody is ever completely right – but even to be approximately
right entails the objective reality of universal and eternal truth.)
*
'Truth' can be defined as 'underlying reality’. Science is not the
only way of discovering truth (for example, philosophy is also about
discovering truth - science being in its origin a sub-specialty of philosophy)
- but unless an activity is trying to discover underlying reality, then
certainly it cannot be science.
But what motivates someone to want to discover the truth about
something?
The great scientists are all very strongly motivated to ‘want to know’ about
reality, and this drove them to great efforts, risk, hardship - and kept them
at their task for decades.
Why scientists should be interested in one thing rather than
another thing remains a mystery – but what is clear is that this interest
cannot be dictated but arises from within – having arisen it can be encouraged
but not re-directed.
Real science is a vocation.
*
Francis Crick commented that you should research that about which
you gossip, James Watson commented that you should avoid subjects which bore
you.
Their point was that science is so difficult, that when
motivation is deficient then problems will not get solved.
You need, you must have, spontaneous positive interest (the
gossip test) and you cannot solve problems that bore you because real science
is too hard to succeed without the benefit of spontaneous interest.
Motivation needs all the help it can get – hence real science
cannot be dictated. It cannot be planned.
The directed provision of research funding and the implementation
of research strategy can certainly make people ‘do research’ in a
particular field; but it cannot make them do real science.
*
But there is an opposite assumption at work in mainstream modern ‘science’; the
idea that professional researchers should properly be motivated by career
incentives such as appointments, pay and promotion – and not by
their intrinsic interest in a problem.
This is rationalized on the basis that personal motivations are a
probable source of bias.
Well, maybe they are – but without personal motivation you don’t
get science at all.
The way to get valid science is not to employ people who care so
little about what they study that they are impartially uninterested in everything
and will believe and work on anything.
The way to get valid science is to have a group of
inevitably-biased people working together to seek the truth – the motivation
to seek truth will find ways to deal with bias, as was seen many times in
the history of science.
In reality, the bureaucrats who run science just do not want vocationally
motivated scientists as employees, since they are intrinsically awkward
individuals - precisely for the reason that their beliefs and activities can
neither easily nor wholly be shaped by career incentives.
*
By contrast, careerist research drones who want to be ‘successful’
will do whatever they are told to do and will not do what they are
punished for doing. Careerist research drones would not, for example, insist on
trying to discover the structure of DNA when they were supposed to be doing
other things – as did Crick and Watson.
Modern pseudo-scientific bureaucrats would try very hard not
to employ anyone with the awkward personality traits of Crick and Watson, and
indeed very few modern researchers are of that type.
Thus everything runs smoothly, people do exactly what they are
supposed to do – and the only problem is that zero real science gets done...
However, that ‘perception’ is easily fixed by public relations,
hype and spin.
The peer review cartel
The modern scientist is supposed to be a docile and obedient
bureaucrat and is trained and selected for that purpose – cheerfully switching
‘interests’ and tasks as required by the changing (or unchanging) imperatives
of funding, the fashions of research and the orders of his master.
What determines a modern scientist’s choice of problem? Essentially it is peer
review – the modern scientist is supposed to do whatever work that the
cartel of peer-review-dominating scientists decide he should do and reward him
for doing.
This will almost certainly involve working as a team member for one or more of
the peer review cartel scientists (or their out-sourced ‘suppliers’); doing
some kind of allocated micro-specialized task of no meaning and zero intrinsic
interest – but one which, supposedly, contributes to the overall project being
managed by the peer review cartel members.
Of course the funders and grant awarders have the major role in
what science gets done, and these are all parts of an interconnected
bureaucratic web of senior professional researchers. The allocation of funding,
hence the direction of research and the subjects deemed acceptable, has long
since been captured by the peer review cartel.
*
Even more importantly than choosing the subject matter of
research, the peer review cartel has captured the ability to define success
in solving scientific problems.
To solve a problem, the cartel of dominant scientists in a field
simply declares that the problem has been solved!
Since peer review is now regarded as the gold standard of science,
when the peer review cartel announces that a problem has been solved, then that
problem has by definition been solved.
Since truth is no longer transcendental but internal to research then nothing
more needs be said: indeed there is nothing more to say. Power is truth (in
modern research).
And anyone who disagrees is not competent to have an opinion, also
by definition.
*
To what does the modern ‘scientist’ aspire? Obviously not to
discover the truth about reality. Instead, he aspires to become a member of the
peer review cartel – one of the group who allocate ‘success’ in science.
In other words, the modern ‘scientist’ aspires to become a
bureaucrat, a manager, a ‘politician’. In yet other words, the modern
‘scientist’ aspires to power – (im)pure and simple.
However, being a modern high level bureaucrat, manager or
politician is incompatible with truthfulness, and dishonesty is incompatible
with science; hence being a successful modern ‘scientist’ is incompatible with
the practice of real science.
Understanding reality
A real scientist needs to want to understand reality - this
necessarily entails first believing in reality (believing that
reality is real), and secondly believing that one ought to discover and
describe reality (which is the specific vocation of a scientist).
*
The belief in reality is a necessary metaphysical belief, which
cannot be denied without contradiction - nonetheless, in modern ruling elite
culture it is frequently denied (this is called nihilism); which is why modern
elite culture is unprecedented in being irrational, self-contradictory (and
self-destroying).
But obviously, a real scientist cannot be a nihilist - whatever
cynical or trendy things he might say or do in public, in his heart he must
have a transcendental belief in the reality of reality and must want to know
something of it.
Thus a real scientist cannot be a member of the modern ruling
elite – therefore, a real scientist in the modern world must be
powerless...
*
Science also involves the metaphysical belief (‘metaphysical’
meaning a necessary assumption which frames the practice of science, and
is not itself part of science) – a belief in the understandability of nature
including the human desire and capacity to understand.
(That is, understandability at some level of approximation, sufficient
understanding - but not necessary detailed or comprehensive understanding.).
Without this belief in the understandability of nature, science
becomes an absurd and impossible attempt to find the one truth among an
infinite number of possible errors.
Nonetheless, in modern elite culture, a belief in the
understandability of nature and human capacity is routinely denied - another
aspect of nihilism. Among many other consequences, this denial destroys the
science which makes possible modern elite culture.
*
Explaining
reality is a second step which may follow understanding, but effective
explaining needs to be preceded by the desire to explain reality accurately,
which itself entails honesty; again because there are an infinite number of possible
explanations varying in accuracy between as close-as-possible to understood
reality; to as far from accurate as you can get-away-with.
*
Modern science is undercut by many things - one is the difficulty
for modern scientists of working according to the proper motivations and
beliefs of a real scientist.
Transcendental beliefs such as the reality of reality and the
desirability of truth are difficult to hold in isolation and in a hostile environment
that imposes multiple pressures to abandon proper motivations to expedience.
It is difficult, in other words, for a modern scientist to work
according to the principles of real science; when to do so requires a lesser or
greater sacrifice of career and status. And when any level of sacrifice
of principles will negate the possibility of real science.
Yet the demands of real science are absolute. There can be no
compromise with truth.
And the punishment for failure to be truthful is simple – failure
of knowledge. No progress in science – but instead loss and destruction of
knowledge.
Real science declined because scientific genius
declined
That science progressed overall, rapidly and by a great deal
between, say, 1700 and 1950 can be assumed.
But what drove this progress?
Scientific progress is talked about in three main ways, depending
on the numbers/ proportion of the population involved in generating this
progress. We could conceptualize science as the product of tiny minority of
creative geniuses, an elite class of professionals, or a mass
population of competence.
*
1. Genius – science as the product
of 10s to 100s of people per generation (for England at its height – much less
for most other places) – a fraction of one percent of the population.
This idea states that science is the product of, depends on, a
relatively small number of geniuses - without whom there would be no significant
progress.
Therefore an age of scientific progress can be boiled down to the
activity of tens or hundreds of geniuses; and the history of science is a list
of great men.
Since little/ nothing is known about how to generate
scientific genius, the task is mainly one of selection of individuals; aiming
to ensure that those who seem, potentially, to posses creative genius are given
the chance to implement it – rather like the ‘methods’ for discovering and
developing top athletes and sportsmen, chess grandmasters, or great singers and
classical musicians.
1. *
2. Elite - 1000s to 10,000s of
people per generation – a few percent of the population.
Science is the product of an elite of highly educated and trained
people, usually found in a relatively small number of elite and
research-orientated institutions, linked in an intensely intercommunicating
network.
This elite are presumed to generate, by their cooperation,
significant scientific progress.
Without this elite, and these elite institutions, there would be
no significant progress.
According to this view, the history of science is a history of
institutions. So the promotion of science is a matter of the creation and
sustenance of elite degrees, elite universities, elite research units etc.
A matter, therefore, of selection of institutions.
*
3. Mass - 100,000s to millions of
people per generation – a large percent of the population, ideally most of the
population.
By this view, science is the product of a 'critical mass' of
scientifically-orientated and educated people spread across a nation or
culture; and whose attitudes and various skills add or synergize to generate
scientific progress. If society as a whole is not sufficiently 'scientific' in
this sense, then there will not be significant progress.
The history of science is seen as a history of gradual
transformation of populations - mainly by educational reform. So the promotion
of science is a matter of science teaching (e.g. in STEM – science,
technology, engineering and mathematics) – to as high a level and for as many
of the population as possible.
A (common) twist on this is the idea that all humans have vast
untapped potential - and that this potential might somehow be activated
- e.g. by the right kind of education; leading to an elite of geniuses, or a
mass-elite, or something...
*
Perhaps the mainstream idea nowadays is a mushy kind of belief/
aspiration that science is essentially elite but that the elite can be expanded
indefinitely by education and increased professionalization.
Another common modern variant is that scientific progress began as based
on individual creative genius, then became elite-driven, and nowadays is a mass
('democratic') movement.
However, this is merely an historical description of what has
actually happened (more or less) to professional research - underpinned
by the unchallenged (but false) assumption that scientific progress has indeed
been maintained throughout this transition.
But there is no reason to accept that assumption of continued
progress (given the vastly increased level and pervasiveness of hype and
dishonesty in science).
Certainly there do seem to be historical examples of scientific
progress without need for a prior scientific mass of the population, or even a
pre-existing elite gathered in elite institutions. It looks very much as if
science is mostly a product of individual genius; and a sufficient
concentration and succession of creative geniuses are the key necessity -
without which scientific progress will not happen.
*
Of course, nowadays there are (approximately) zero geniuses in
science, so admitting that genius is necessary to significant scientific
progress entails admitting that we are not making progress.
Again: admitting that there are no geniuses means admitting
there is no progress...
which admission would devastate all scientific careers,
since these careers depend upon the conviction and expectation of continued
progress.
Therefore, the necessity for genius in science is an hypotheses
that cannot be entertained.
*
Nonetheless, my reading of the history of science is that a
sufficient supply of genius really is necessary to significant scientific
progress (although history has not always recorded the identities of the
presumed geniuses).
At any rate, science has often made significant progress without
elites in the modern sense, and elites often fail to make progress; and the
idea that scientific progress arises from mass education of the masses is very
obviously sheer moonshine, without a shred of evidence in support...
Furthermore, if geniuses are necessary for real scientific progress,
and if real scientific progress is necessary for modernity (i.e. a
society based-on growth - such that growth in productivity will out-run
population growth)...
And if (as it seems) there are (for whatever reason) no more
geniuses…
Then scientific progress has
already stopped and will not re-start (unless there can again be not just a
few but a sufficiency of real geniuses in science) – and modern society will in
due course collapse due to the usually-operative ‘Malthusian’ mechanism that
the weight of population will grow to be in excess of economic (especially
food) production.
Human capability peaked decades ago, and has
since declined
What is the ‘evidence’ for decline in science?
Clearly, such evidence must be of the ‘common sense’ variety,
since scientific evaluations are precisely what is under question – we know
they are poisoned by dishonesty, hype and spin.
Here is one item: I suspect that overall human capability
(leaving aside specific domains) reached its peak or plateau around 1965-75 –
at the time of the Apollo moon landings – and has been declining ever since.
*
This may sound bizarre or just plain false, but the argument is
simple. That business of landing men on the moon and bringing them back alive
was the supreme achievement of human capability, the most difficult
problem ever solved by humans.
40 years ago we could do it – and repeatedly – but since then we
have not been to the moon, and I suggest the real reason we have not
been to the moon since 1972 is that we cannot any longer do it. Humans have
lost the capability.
*
Of course, the standard line is that humans stopped going to the
moon only because we no longer wanted to go to the moon (done that, got
the T-shirt...), or could not afford to, or something…
But I am suggesting that all this is so much hot air, merely
excuses for not doing something which we cannot do.
*
It is as if an eighty year old ex-professional-cyclist was to
claim that the reason he had stopped competing in the Tour de France was
that he had now had found better ways to spend his time and money.
This may be true; but does not refute the fact that an 80 year old
could not successfully compete in international cycling races even if he wanted
to.
And this fact would not be altered if the 80 year old had
undergone extensive plastic surgery and offered in evidence carefully
‘airbrushed’ photographs that made him look as if he was just 45.
And this fact would not be altered if he was able to do other
things instead (such as building better computers or making better
televisions).
And the fact would not be altered even if he presented the
testimony of a panel of prestigious doctors and physiologists who swore on oath
that he could win the Tour de France if he really wanted to.
He may look like he can do it, he may be able to do other things,
he may swear that he could do it if he wanted to – but the telling fact is that
he does not do it.
*
Human capability partly depends on technology. A big task requires
a variety of appropriate and interlocking technologies – the absence of any one
vital technology would prevent attainment.
I presume that much technology has continued to improve since 1975
– so technological decline is not likely to be the reason for failure of
capability.
But, however well planned, human capability in complex tasks also
depends on ‘on-the-job’ problem-solving – the ability to combine expertise and
creativity to deal with unforeseen situations.
And human capability also depends on attitude: with the primary
imperative of getting-the-job-done.
*
It is on-the-job problem-solving and getting-the-job-done
attitudes which have declined so sharply over recent decades – declined to the
point of rendering Western societies helpless in the face of difficulties
which could easily have been solved several decades ago.
It might be asserted that these are trivial psychological
factors, which could be changed if and when necessary. But it seems that these
psychological factors cannot be discarded even when it is necessary
– it is, after all, so much easier to deny the reality of the difficulties,
simply to look the other way, do something else...
*
On the job problem-solving means having the best people doing the
most important jobs.
For example, if it had not been Neil Armstrong at the controls of
the first Apollo 11 lunar lander, but had instead been somebody of lesser
ability, decisiveness, courage and creativity – the mission would either have
failed or aborted.
If both the astronauts and NASA ground staff had been anything
less than superb, then the Apollo 13 mission would have led to loss of life.
But since the 1970s there has been a decline in the quality of
people in the key jobs in NASA, and elsewhere – because organizations no longer
seek to find and use the best people as their ideal. They are not even trying
to find the best people.
What do they do instead of trying to find the best people?
All sorts of things – for example they try to be ‘diverse’ in various ways
(age, sex, race, nationality etc).
And also the people in the key jobs, even when
they are the best people, are no longer able to decide and command; due to the
expansion of rules, committees and the erosion of individual responsibility and
autonomy.
*
By 1986, and the Challenger space shuttle disaster, it was clear that humans
had declined in capability – since the disaster was fundamentally caused by
managers and committees being in control of NASA rather than individual
experts.
It was around the 1970s that the human spirit began to be
overwhelmed by bureaucracy (although the trend had been growing for many
decades).
Since the mid-1970s the rate of progress has declined in physics,
biology and the medical sciences – and some of these have gone into reverse, so
that the practice of science in some areas has overall gone backwards, valid
knowledge has been lost and replaced with phony fashionable triviality and
dishonest hype.
Some of the biggest areas of science – medical research, molecular
biology, neuroscience, epidemiology, climate research – are almost wholly
trivial or bogus. They have failed to deliver on a truly catastrophic
scale.
Never have so many resources have been expended with so little to
show for it: Stonehenge and the Pyramids may not do much, but at least
they are still there...
*
This broad general failure in core objectives is not compensated
by a few islands of progress, e.g. in computerization and the invention of the
internet.
Capability must cover all the bases, psycho-social as well as technical, and
depends not on a single advanced area but all-round advancement in all
necessary areas.
Human capability then and now
The fact is that human no longer do - can no longer do -
many things we used to be able to do: land on the moon, swiftly win wars
against weak opposition and then control the defeated nation, secure national
borders, discover ‘breakthrough’ medical treatments, prevent crime, design and
build to a tight deadline, educate people so they are ready to work before the
age of 22, suppress piracy on the high seas...
50 years ago Western societies would aim to have the smartest, best trained,
most experienced and most creative people they could find (given human
imperfections) in position to take responsibility, make decisions and act upon
them in pursuit of a positive goal.
That is what they were trying to do.
Now, we are not even trying.
And since we are not even trying to do the job, naturally the job
will not be done.
*
Now we have dull and docile committee members
chosen partly with an eye to affirmative action and partly to generate positive
media coverage, whose major priority is not to do the job but to avoid personal
responsibility and prevent side-effects and to build careers; pestered at every
turn by an irresponsible and aggressive media and grandstanding politicians out
to score popularity points; all of whom are hemmed-about by vast and proliferating
regulations, such that – whatever they do do, or do not do,
whether they succeed or fail – they will be in breach of some rule or another
and vulnerable to open-ended sanctions.
*
So we should be honest about the fact that human do not anymore fly
to the moon because humans cannot anymore fly to the moon.
Also noteworthy is that the deepest manned ocean descent of about
10.9 kilometres into the Mariana Trench, was as long ago as 1960; and humans
have never again been as deep during the past half century.
Humans have failed to prevent or suppress the re-emergence of high
seas piracy on a large scale because we nowadays cannot do it - although humans
solved the problem 150 years ago.
And we cannot solve new problems either,
since these require a combination of attitudes and freedoms that we can no
longer imagine, or which we fear more than the problems themselves. In the past
the average experts were both smarter and more creative than we are now, and
these experts would then have been in a position to do the needful.
Measuring human capability: Moonshot versus
'Texas Sharpshooter'
But is the Moonshot really a valid measure of human capability?
Yes. The reason that the Moonshot is a valid measure of human
capability is that the problem was difficult and was not chosen but imposed.
*
The objective of landing men on the moon (and bringing them safely
back) was not chosen by scientists and engineers as being something already within
their capability – but was a problem imposed on them by politicians.
The desirability of the Moonshot is irrelevant to this
point. I used to be strongly in favour of space exploration, now I have
probably turned against it – but my own views are not relevant to the use of
the Moonshot as the ultimate evidence of human capability.
Other examples of imposed problems include the Manhattan Project
for devising an atomic bomb – although in this instance the project was
embarked upon precisely because senior scientists judged that the problem could
possibly, maybe probably, be solved; and therefore that the US ought to solve
it first before Germany did so.
But, either way, the problem of building an atomic bomb was also
successfully solved.
Again, the desirability of atomic bombs is not the point here –
the point is that it was a measure of human capability in solving difficult
imposed problems.
*
Since the Moonshot, there have been several difficult problems
imposed by politicians on scientists that have not been solved: such as
finding a ‘cure for cancer’ (or the common cold) and ‘understanding the brain’.
These two problems had vastly more monetary and manpower resources
(although vastly less talent and creativity) thrown at them than was the case
for either the Moonshot or Manhattan Project.
But modern technological advances are not imposed problems;
they are instead examples of the Texas Sharpshooter fallacy.
*
The joke of the Texas Sharpshooter is that he fires his gun many
times into a barn door, then draws a target over the bullet holes, with the
bulls-eye over the closest cluster of bullet holes.
In other words the Texas Sharpshooter makes it look as if he had
been aiming at the bulls-eye and had hit it, when in fact he drew the bulls-eye
only after he took the shots.
Modern science and engineering is like that. People do research
and development, and then proclaim triumphantly that whatever they have done is
a breakthrough. They have achieved whatever-happens-to-come-out-of-R&D; and
then they spin, hype and market whatever-happens-to-come-out-of-R&D as if
it were a major breakthrough.
In other words, modern R&D triumphantly solves a retrospectively
designated problem, the problem being generated to validate
whatever-happens-to-come-out-of-R&D.
*
The Human Genome Project was an example of Texas Sharpshooting
masquerading as human capability.
Sequencing the human genome was not a matter of solving an imposed
problem, nor any other kind of real world problem, but was merely doing a
bit faster what was already happening.
*
Personally, I am no fan of Big Science, indeed I regard the
success of the Manhattan Project as the beginning of the end for real science.
But those who are keen that humanity solve big problems and who
boast about our ability to do so; need to acknowledge that humanity has
apparently become much worse, not better, at solving big problems over the past
40 years – so long as we judge success only in terms of solving imposed
problems which we do not already know how to solve, and so long as we ignore
the trickery of the many Texas Sharpshooters among modern scientists and
engineers.
The Texas Sharpshooter society of secular
modernity
As I said, the Texas Sharpshooter fallacy is a joke which suggests
that the TS fires his gun many times into a barn door, then afterwards draws a
target over the bullet holes.
But the sharpshooter fallacy is nowadays unavoidable and
everywhere, it characterizes secular modern society throughout, because secular
modern society has no aim but instead idealizes process and retrofits
aim to outcome.
Indeed, the Texas Sharpshooter strategy is the master theory of
our phase of late modernity – the persuasion of people that whatever has
happened is what they wanted and what was intended.
*
Secular moderns - in public discourse - 'believe in' things like freedom,
or democracy, or equality, or progress - but these are processes, not aims.
Aims are not prescribed in advance and progress checked-against
them – instead, aims are retrospectively ascribed to whatever emerges from
process.
In this respect professional science is merely a typical aspect of
modern life – real science has been assimilated into mainstream contemporary
life.
*
It happens all the time: abolition of slavery emerged from the
American Civil War therefore people retrospectively ascribe liberation as its
purpose. Destruction of the death camps emerged from the second world war, so
the liberation of the Jews is ascribed as its purpose.
Libertarians 'believe in' freedom not as a means to some end, but
as a process which by definition leads to the best ends; so that they 'believe
in' whatever comes out of the process.
*
The modern attitude is that the best thing is for science to be
well funded and to do what science does, and whatever comes out of the process
of science is retrospectively defined as 'truth'.
In practice, science is defined as whatever scientists do,
and what scientists do is defined as generating truth.
Texas Sharpshooter Fallacy...
*
Or law. Law is a process, and justice is defined as that which
results from the process of law. Modern laws may feel revoltingly unjust; but
lacking a transcendental concept of justice, nothing more can be said. Justice
is what justice does.
TSF...
*
Or education. What is education? The answer is ‘what happens at
school and college’. And whatever happens at school and college is what counts
as education. Since what happens at school and college changes, then the
meaning of education changes. But since education is not aiming at anything
in particular, it is merely ‘what happens at schools and colleges’, then
these changes cannot be evaluated. Whatever happens is retrospectively defined
as what needed to happen.
TSF...
*
Or economics. Economic ‘growth’ is pursued as the good, and
whatever comes out of economics is defined as prosperity. What people 'want' is
known only by what they get - their wants are retrospectively ascribed. If what
is being measured and counted grows, then this is defined as growing
prosperity. So the economy fifty years ago wanted more A, B and C but the
modern economy instead provides X, Y and Z – however, economists
retrospectively re-draw the target around X, Y and Z and proclaim the triumph
of economics. The economy did not provide ABC, but this is taken to prove that
ABC was not really wanted; instead the economy provided XYZ which is
taken to reveal people’s true preferences.
TSF...
*
This is, of course, paradoxical; but it is not just paradoxical - it is
nonsense.
The primacy of process is simple nonsense – it is sleight-of-hand,
it is bait-and-switch. It is trying to do without aims because all aims point
to the necessity for underpinning justifications for those aims. Since modern
society regards clear and explicit aims as merely arbitrary and subjective
statements, and because aims (except when platitudinous) are divisive; it
cannot agree on aims and regards it as dangerous to try.
Secular modernity is fundamentally (not accidentally, not
reformably) based on the Texas Sharpshooter fallacy, and the fallacy is simple
and obvious
However, since the fallacy is intrinsic and pervasive, it must be
concealed; and it is concealed.
Since collapse happened to Classics, it could
happen to science
Since professional science is not longer providing the
breakthroughs in efficiency that are necessary to sustain modernity, then
modernity will collapse; we will, in other words, return to the Malthusian Trap
in which increasing population will cause reducing standard of living (or
violence or disease) until such a point that the population has come into line
with resources.
But, before that point, it is probable (not definite) that
professional science will itself collapse – simply because it is on the one
hand a waste of resources (costs) and on the other hand these resources are needed
for other purposes (opportunity costs).
*
I find that people simply cannot take seriously that Science would
collapse down to a small fraction of its current (vast, bloated) size. Despite
that real science is so recent, and is so fragile (so vulnerable to corruption)
– people assume that it must be eternal because it so useful.
But why people imagine that something will survive merely because
it is useful, in the face of so many counter examples in their own experience
of useful things disappearing, is hard to fathom...
And there is a recent precedent for the collapse
of the dominant intellectual culture: Classics.
*
The study of Greek and Roman culture - language, history,
literature, philosophy - was the dominant secular intellectual activity in the
West for many hundreds of years and the teaching of Latin was at the core of
the educational curriculum for a couple of millennia.
Latin was the mark of A Gentleman, especially A
Scholar – Classics was the highest status form of knowledge, the main
(sometimes he only) subject taught at the best schools and universities.
*
In England, when it was the top country and culture, Classics
pretty much monopolized the curriculum in the Public Schools, Grammar Schools
and Oxford University (Cambridge focused on mathematics - but had plenty of
Classicists too). New subjects like Science, modern languages and modern
history had to fight for space in the curriculum.
Right up into the mid 20th century, the most prestigious general degree in
England was the Oxford four year Classics degree – it was the premier
'qualification' for elite ruling class professions.
The 'two cultures' debate of the late 1950s and
early 1960s marked the tipping-point when Science began to dominate Classics in
general cultural discourse. Classics more-or-less retained prestige for another
generation, after which it very suddenly collapsed, in the 1980s.
*
The classics have now dwindled to the status of a hobby, taught in
few schools and very seldom given much prominence.
Most UK universities have all-but abandoned the subject except at
a ‘taster’ level - only a handful of courses at a few places can find
undergraduates with any background or competence in Latin (even fewer in
Greek); so most modern 'Classics' degrees are built on no foundations in three
years; teaching from a basis of zero knowledge.
Advocates of Classics find it ever harder to
justify their subject as worthy of study - certainly there is no automatic
deference towards it, no assumption of its superiority.
*
So, in the space of about 250 years, from the time of Samuel
Johnson - when he was apologetic about writing in English rather than Latin and
focusing his dictionary on the English vernacular - until now, Classics have
dwindled from unchallenged dominance to insignificance in general Western
culture.
*
Classics was quietly dwindling in cultural importance for a few
hundred years (at least since Shakespeare outstripped all rivals using the
vernacular), and this was becoming ever more apparent from the mid 19th
century; but at least as recently as the time of the great English Classics
professor (and poet) Houseman (1859-1936) it looked as if the subject was on
the verge of a breakthrough (using 'modern' scholarship).
And of course classical scholarship has continued throughout all
this decline, pouring-out research books and scholarly articles for a dwindling
audience of other scholars.
But despite all this, Classics has undeniably
collapsed.
*
My point is that if it seems unimaginable to many people that
Science really could collapse from dominance into insignificance in just a few
decades, then these people should think about what happened to Classics. The
signs are there for those who look behind the hype.
Of course a scientist feels that the real importance of Classics was trivial
compared with Science – that the modern world depends on Science.
Quite true; but then the ancient world depended on Classics, and
the collapse of Classics was linked with the collapse of traditional society.
The collapse of Science is linked with the collapse of modernity - both as
cause and as consequence.
Chargaff on the loss of human pace and scale in
science
Referring to his first twelve years at Columbia University, USA,
Erwin Chargaff (1905-2002) said:
“The more than sixty regular papers published during that period dealt with a
very wide field of biochemistry, as it was then understood; and a few of them
may even have contributed a little to the advance of science, which, at that
time, was still slow, i.e., it had human proportions... Nevertheless, when I
look back on what I did during those twelve years, there come to mind the words
ascribed to St. Thomas Aquinas: Omnia quae scripsi paleae mihi videntur. All he
had written seemed to him as chaff.
“When I was young, I was required – and it was easy – to go back
to the origins of our science. The bibliographies of chemical and biological
papers often included reference to work done forty or fifty years earlier. One
felt oneself part of a gently growing tradition, growing at a rate that the
human mind could encompass, vanishing at a rate it could apprehend.
“Now, however, in our miserable scientific mass society, nearly
all discoveries are born dead; papers are tokens in a power game, evanescent
reflections on the screen of a spectator sport, new items that do not outlive
the day on which they appeared. Our sciences have become forcing houses for a
market that in reality does not exist, creating, with the concomitant complete
break in tradition, a truly Babylonian confusion of mind and language.
“Nowadays, scientific tradition hardly reaches back for more than
three or four years. The proscenium looks the same as before, but the scenery
keeps on changing as in a fever dream; no sooner is one backdrop in place than
it is replaced by an entirely different one. The only thing that experience can
now teach is that it has become worthless.
“One could ask whether a fund of knowledge, such as a scientific
discipline, can exist without a living tradition. In any event, in many areas
of science which I am able to survey, this tradition has disappeared. It is,
hence, no exaggeration and no coquettish humility if I conclude that the work
we did thirty or forty years ago – with all the engagement that honest effort
could provide – is dead and gone.”
Erwin Chargaff – Heraclitean Fire, 1978.
*
From this I note: “the advance of science … was still slow, i.e.,
it had human proportions. … One felt oneself part of a gently growing
tradition, growing at a rate that the human mind could encompass, vanishing at
a rate it could apprehend.”
That is the pace of real
science.
“…in our miserable scientific mass society, nearly all discoveries
are born dead; papers are tokens in a power game, evanescent reflections on the
screen of a spectator sport, new items that do not outlive the day on which
they appeared…”
In contrast, the “miserable scientific mass society” of modern
research does not operate at the pace of real science, but at the pace of management.–
Six monthly appraisals, yearly job plans, three yearly grants and so on. All
evaluations being conducted and determined by committee and bureaucracy, by
votes and algorithms, according to check-box lists of objectives and outcomes -
rather than by individual judgment.
“Our sciences have become forcing houses for a market that in
reality does not exist…”
Nobody really wants what modern science provides, there is
no real need for it; which is why modern science is dishonest – from top
to bottom: modern science must engage in public relations, hype, spin – lies –
in order to persuade ‘the market’ that it really wants whatever stuff the
‘forcing houses’ of modern science are relentlessly churning-out.
“...honest effort...”
A two-word definition of real science.
Delbruck on the moral qualities of science
Max Delbruck - 1906-1981. Nobel Prize 1969
Question: Does scientific research by itself foster high moral
qualities in men?
Delbruck's answer: "Scientific research by itself fosters one
high moral quality: that you should be reasonably honest. This quality is in
fact displayed to a remarkable extent. Although many of the things that you
read in scientific journals are wrong, one does assume automatically that the
author at least believed he was right."
(Quoted p282 in Thinking about Science: Max Delbruck and the origins
of molecular biology. EP Fischer & C Lipson. 1988)
*
Delubruck was talking in 1971, forty years ago (a mere 40
years ago!) and he was one of the most well-connected of twentieth century
scientists, a kind of godfather to molecular biology, and a man of great
personal integrity.
So Delbruck was in a position to know what he was talking about.
And, in 1971, he was able to state that scientific research by
itself fosters the high moral quality that you should be reasonably honest. And
that this quality is in fact displayed to a remarkable extent.
And that when reading journals scientists could and did assume
that the authors were telling the truth as they saw it.
Only 40 years ago Delbruck could state that scientists were in
fact, in reality, in practice - honest...
Nobody of Delbruck’s integrity in Delbruck’s position could say
the same today.
Micro-specialization and the infinite
perpetuation of error
Science, real science, is itself a specialization of philosophy.
After which science itself specialized – at first into physical and natural
sciences, and then into ever-finer divisions.
Scientific specialization is generally supposed to benefit the
precision and validity of knowledge within specializations, but at the
cost of these specializations becoming narrower, and loss of integration between
specializations.
In other words, as specialization proceeds, people supposedly know more and
more about less and less - the benefit being presumed to be more knowledge
within each domain; the cost that no single person has a general
understanding.
*
However, I think that there is no benefit, but instead harm, from
specialization beyond a certain point – an imprecise but long-since-passed
point.
Nowadays, people do not really know more, even within their
specialization – often they know nothing valid at all; almost everything
they think they know is wrong, because undercut by fundamental errors intrinsic
and yet invisible to that specialty.
The clear cut benefits of specialization apply only to the
early stages such as the career differentiation in the early 20th century -
the era when there was a threefold division of university science degrees into
Physics, Chemistry and Biology.
It is much less obvious that real science benefited from
subdivision of each of these into two or three (e.g. Physics into Theoretical
and Applied, Chemistry into Organic and Inorganic; Biology into Zoology and
Botany).
But since the 1960s scientific specialization has now gone far,
far beyond this point, and the process is now almost wholly disadvantageous.
We are now in an era of micro-specialization, with dozens
of subdivisions within sciences. Biology, for example, fragmented into
biochemistry, molecular biology, genetics, neuroscience, anatomy, physiology,
pharmacology, cell biology, marine biology, ecology...
*
Part of this is simply the low average and peak level of ability,
motivation and honesty in most branches of modern science. The number of
scientists has increased by more than an order of magnitude – clearly this has
an effect on quality.
Scientific training and conditions have become prolonged and dull
and collectivist – deterring creative and self-motivated people. And these
changes have happened in an era when the smartest kids tended not to gravitate
to science, as they did in the early 20th century, but instead to professions
such as medicine and law, and into the financial sector.
In round numbers, it seems likely that more than ninety percent of
modern ‘scientists’ are worse than the worst scientists of 60 years ago.
However there is a more basic and insoluble problem about
micro-specialization. This is that micro-specialization is about
micro-validation – which can neither detect nor correct gross errors in its basic
suppositions.
*
In the world of micro-specialization that is a
modern scientific career, each specialist’s attention is focused on technical
minutiae and the application of conventional proxy measures and operational
definitions. Most day-to-day research-related discussion (when it is not about
fund-raising) is troubleshooting – getting techniques and machines to
work, managing personnel and coordinating projects...
Specific micro-specialist fields are built-around specific
methodologies - for no better ultimate reason than 'everybody else' does the
same, and (lacking any real validity to their activities) there must be some
kind of arbitrary ‘standard’ against which people are judged for career
purposes (judging people by real scientific criteria of discovering truths
is of course not done).
('Everybody else' here means the cartel of dominant Big Science
researchers who control peer review - appointments, promotions, grants,
publications etc. - in that micro-speciality.)
Thus, micro-specialists are ultimately technicians and/or
bureaucrats; thus they cannot even understand fatal objections and
comprehensive refutations of their standard paradigms when these originate from
adjacent areas of science. So long as their own specific technique has been
conducted according to prevailing micro-specialist professional practice, they
equate the outcome with ‘truth’ and assume its validity and intrinsic value.
In a nutshell, micro-specialization allows a situation to develop
where the whole of a vast area of science is bogus knowledge; and for this
reality of total bogosity to be intrinsically and permanently invisible and
incomprehensible to the participants in that science.
*
If we then combine this situation with the prevalent professional
research notion that only micro-specialists are competent to evaluate
the domain of their micro-speciality – and add-in the continual
fragmentation of research into ever-smaller micro-specialties - then we have a
recipe for permanent and intractable error.
*
Vast and exponentially-growing scientific enterprises have
consumed vast resources without yielding any substantive progress at the level
of in-your-face common sense evaluations; and the phenomenon continues for
time-spans of whole generations, and there is no end in sight (short of the
collapse of science-as-a-whole).
According to the analysts of classical science, science was
supposed to be uniquely self-correcting - in practice, now, thanks in part to
micro-specialization, it is not self-correcting at all – except at the
trivial and misleadingly reassuring level of micro-defined technical glitches
and slip-ups.
Either what we call science nowadays is not 'real science' or else
real science has mutated into something which is a mechanism for the
perpetuation of error.
The idea of science as a truth-machine
As I survey the wondrous corruption of scientists, it seems that most
of them fall pretty soon into the obvious dishonesty of hype and spin,
selection and exaggeration.
But not all do so; and among those decent scientists who strive to
be honest while pursuing a successful career I perceive an alternative pattern
which is only indirectly, and as it were accidentally dishonest: a
pseudo-solution which unintentionally makes matters worse, by camouflaging
flagrant dishonesty and rejecting real science.
It is a strategy which is often pursued with high ideals, a clear
conscience and in a spirit of modesty, although it is in operation
anti-scientific in spirit and effect.
This strategy is to replace honesty with precision, to replace
truth-seeking with a quest for technical accuracy.
*
Perhaps the root of this error is the notion that there is such a
thing as ‘scientific method’ (detachable from the individuals who practice
science); and that if this scientific method is strictly adhered-to, then
the result will be valid science.
In parody, this is the terribly mistaken view that science is a
truth-machine: the idea that if you do science properly then you
will manufacture ‘truth’ reliably and cumulatively.
The idea that if you perform observations and experiments
according to the approved principles, then this will lead to ‘facts’.
And if you feed these ‘facts’ into the correct analytical and
statistical procedures (‘scientific methodology’) then what comes out of
the machine will be objective truth.
The idea that although the exact output may not precisely be known
in advance, the process by which valid outputs are generated is
understood to be controllable, and therefore it can confidently
be predicted that the result of this process will be valuable knowledge.
In sum, this is the mainstream modern view that research input
reliably leads to real scientific output (albeit with varying degrees of
efficiency).
(This reasoning justifies the usual practice for measuring science
by measuring inputs – that is, measuring science by measuring how many
resources - grants, personnel, capital - are expended on supposedly-scientific goals.
The inputs are simply assumed to result in valid and relevant outputs of
knowledge so long as approved procedures are strictly followed.)
*
This is, indeed the basic underlying ‘model’ for modern science,
especially Big Science – and it leads to the mainstream assumption that the
constraint on science is resources. The model assumes that – if you have
research managers who are deploying resources (manpower, machines etc) doing
the right things - then resources will be transformed into knowledge.
There may be disagreement about the efficiency of this
process, but the assumption is very widely held that spending a lot of money on
a problem will accumulate knowledge towards its solution – so long as
the researchers are competent and rigorous (and that competence and rigour are
themselves defined as products of resources – i.e. educational and training
resources).
Indeed, rigour is a key word here – because rigour is
defined in term of exact adherence to predetermined method, technique,
procedure – and this implies that science ideally ought to be made wholly
explicit, planned down to its finest detail, and done in accordance with plans.
And this is, indeed, the way that research funding is managed –
‘scientists’ are compelled to submit detailed plans, which are approved or
disapproved.
Science is seen as a process of implementation, the process
is seen as something explicit and managed, and the role of the individual
researcher is – in a nutshell – obedience.
*
It is obvious that this typically modern way of doing professional
research – based on the concept of research as a ‘truth-machine’ - bears zero
relationship to how real science was done in the past, during the golden age of
science - when science was small scale, individualistic, cheap, efficient and
led to many breakthroughs; and it is also obvious that this resource- and
organization-orientated way of doing research is derived not from science but
is instead the characteristic modus operandi of bureaucracies.
And it is worth asking what evidence there is or was that
scientific research would be done better, valid knowledge better generated, in
this bureaucratic fashion than in the effective mode of the past?
And the answer is equally obvious that there is no such
evidence; but, on the contrary, conclusive evidence that scientific
research is done much worse or not at all with this bureaucratic mode –
less efficiently and less effectively, indeed mostly done with zero or negative
real world outcomes – than when research was done as real science.
*
The deep problem with a technical focus on rigour is that method
is a means not an end.
A scientific problem does not dictate a specific method; indeed
the solution to a problem often comes from a new, non-obvious and unanticipated
method; and the solution to a problem is often best known exactly by the
convergence of several methods.
Furthermore, methods are substantially constrained by manpower and
technology (especially by the development of machines, including computers),
and a focus on method becomes a race to assemble the largest teams and be the
first to deploy the new and ‘improved’ technology. Linked is the assumption
that old technology and methods are intrinsically unable to answer the
questions. Whereas old technologies and methods may well be able to answer the
questions if creative scientific genius is added to the mix – or even
just sincere truth-seeking.
*
Yet, as often as not, modern scientific ‘fields’ (research groups,
appointments, journals, conferences) are defined by their technologies.
Presumably this is helpful in terms of proximate goals - trouble-shooting
methods; but destroys the possibility of real science.
Real science does not happen unless scientists are truth seekers
and truth speakers, and truth seeking is an end not a means – truth is not
confined by methods; and truth is a whole, not a part – an excess focus on one
aspect is equivalent to the gross exaggeration of one virtue at the expense of
virtuous-ness.
So factual technical rigour, being measurable, on the one hand
obscures all other forms of dishonesty– so that people who are not even
trying to discover or tell the truth but instead pursuing full-on careerism
can nonetheless feel themselves to be self-denying paragons of virtue due to
their slavish and uncritical submission to fashionable but arbitrary technical
demands; while on the other hand it also rejects real science as being
insufficiently rigorous in terms of its having lower precision in the approved
technical domain.
And, because science has been fragmented into micro-specialties,
these errors are ineradicable – there is no progress through
self-correction, merely the fashion-driven progression of new techniques.
Zombie science
Since modern researchers have abandoned the core ethic of truth
seeking, most ‘scientists’ are quite willing to pursue wrong ideas so long as
they are rewarded for doing so with sufficient career incentives.
The primary criterion of the ‘validity’ of a modern research field
is therefore, in practice, the probability that working in it will be likely to
benefit your career.
*
Nowadays, when a new idea is launched, it is unlikely to win
converts unless early-adopters are rewarded in an upfront and obvious fashion –
typically with incentives such as research funding, the opportunity to publish
in prestigious journals, and the promise of increased status exemplified by
interest, admiration and respect from other researchers.
This is the currency of science – the tokens used to exchange for
status, jobs, salary, promotions, prizes...
Therefore new research fields and theories may with extraordinary rapidity
become popular and even dominant purely and simply because adoption is
reinforced by career incentives.
Scientific strengths or scientific weaknesses are nowadays
strictly irrelevant.
*
In terms of the classical theory of science; worthless theories
(e.g. theories that are incoherent or fail to predict observations) should be
demolished by sceptical (or jealous) competitor scientists, who will denounce
the weaknesses of merely-fashionable theories in person, in conferences and
(especially) in print – in the scientific record, the ‘literature’.
However, in practice it seems that even the most conclusive
‘hatchet jobs’ done on phoney theories will fail to kill, or even weaken, them
- when the phoney theories are backed-up with sufficient career incentives.
Scientists gravitate to where the money is; and the paraphernalia of specialist
conferences (to present results at), journals (to publish in) and academic jobs
(to work in) will follow the money as night follows day; so long as the funding
stream is sufficiently strong, deep and sustained.
Classical scientific theory has it that a wrong hypothesis will be
rejected when it fails to predict ‘reality’ as determined by controlled
observations and experiments. But such a catastrophe can be deferred almost
indefinitely by the elaboration of secondary hypotheses to explain why failing
to fit the facts is not – after all – fatal to the theory; but instead merely
implies the need for a more complex theory – which then requires further
testing, and extra funding, and generates more paid work for the bogus
believers.
Furthermore, since the new version of the bogus theory, with its
many auxiliary secondary hypotheses, is so complex – this complexity makes it
that much harder to test; indeed conclusive tests may become impossible, even
in principle, since there are no precise predictions. All of which has the
effect of putting-off indefinitely the time when a bogus theory needs to be
abandoned.
(Meanwhile, a much simpler rival theory – i.e. that the first
theory is phoney, and always was phoney, and this is why it so singularly fails
to predict reality – is regarded as simplistic, crass, merely a sign of lack of
sophistication …)
*
After a while, lavish funding creates powerful interest groups
associated with the phoney theory - including the reputations of numerous
scientists who are now successful and powerful on the back of the phoney
theory, and who by-now control the peer review process (including allocation of
grants, publications and jobs) so there is a powerful disincentive against
upsetting the apple cart. Indeed, the system of peer review sustains the phoney
theory on the basis that turkeys do not vote for Christmas.
What is the function of Zombie science?
When a branch of science based on incoherent, false or phoney
theories is serving a useful but non-scientific purpose it may be
kept-going by continuous transfusions of cash from those whose non-scientific
interests it serves.
For example, if a branch of pseudo-science based on a phoney
theory is nonetheless valuable for political purposes (e.g. to justify a
government intervention such as a new tax) or for marketing purposes (to
provide the rationale for a marketing campaign) then real science expires and a
‘zombie science’ evolves.
Zombie science is science that is dead but will not lie down.
It keeps twitching and lumbering around so that (from a distance, and with your
eyes half-closed) zombie science looks much like real science. But in fact the
zombie has no life of its own; it is animated and moved only by the incessant
pumping of funds.
*
Real science is coherent – and testable (testing
being a matter of checking coherence with the result of past and future
observations).
Real science finds its use, and gets its validation, from common
sense evaluation and being deployed in technology.
Real science is validated (contingently) insofar as it leads to
precise predictions that later come true; and leads to new ways of solving
pressing problems and making useful changes in the world.
But zombie science is not coherent, therefore
cannot be tested; its predications are vague or in fact retrospective summaries
rather than predictions.
*
In a nutshell, zombie science is supported because it is useful
propaganda; trading on the prestige which real science used-to have and
which zombie science falsely claims for itself.
Zombie science is deployed in arenas such as political rhetoric,
public administration, management, public relations, marketing and the mass
media generally. It persuades, it constructs taboos, it buttresses rhetorical
attempts to shape opinion.
Furthermore, most zombie sciences are supported by moral
imperatives – to doubt the zombie science is therefore labelled as wicked,
reckless, a tool of sinister and destructive forces.
To challenge zombie science is not merely to attack the
livelihoods of zombie scientists (which, considering their consensus-based
power, is itself dangerous) – but opens the attacker to being labelled a
luddite, demagogue, anti-science, a denialist!
For all its incoherence and scientific worthlessness, zombie
science therefore often comes across in the sound bite world of the mass media
as being more plausible than real science; and it is precisely the
superficial face-plausibility which in actuality is the sole and sufficient
purpose of zombie science.
The expectation of growth in scientific
knowledge
We have become used to growth in scientific knowledge, and have
come to expect growth in scientific knowledge – scientific progress.
This expectation in scientific progress at first shaped reality
and eventually displaced reality.
The link between expectation and actuality was broken and the
world of assumptions took over.
*
The expectation that scientific knowledge will grow almost
inevitably (given adequate 'inputs' of personnel and funding) is epitomized by
the professionalization of scientific research (making scientific research a
career, then making research jobs part of a bureaucracy) and the normal career
expectation of regular and frequent and measurable outputs – especially
research publications.
The expectation of regular and frequent research publication would
only make sense if it was assumed that scientific knowledge was accumulating in
a predictable fashion.
*
Because of what happened in the past, we nowadays expect an
open-ended growth in the number of scientific publications over time, and a
growth in the totality of citations (references to previous research).
These quantitative increases are at bottom fuelled by increases in
the numbers of professional scientists which drives the number of
journals for publishing science.
According to analysis by Michael Mabe, each researcher generates
approximately one-paper-per-year (controlling for number of authors per paper);
and this has not changed significantly over the decades.
Leaving aside quality – it seems that the expansion of scientific
publication and the growth in journals is merely a consequence of the expansion
of manpower.
*
By assuming that growth in researchers and publications will
continue, we implicitly assume that there is an unbounded quantity of new and
useful science waiting to be discovered and an unrestricted pool of people
capable of making discoveries.
The economist Paul Romer – and others – built this into theories
of the modern economy – the argument is that continued growth in science and
technology fuels continual improvement in productivity (economic output per
person) and therefore growth in the economy. Some of this economic growth is
invested into science (education and employment of personnel and capital
equipment) to drive further economic growth.
The idea is: Increased science leads to increased productivity
leads to increased science.
The idea is that we are continually getting better at
scientific discovery, because we are continually investing more in
scientific discovery, therefore modern society is enabled to continue
economic growth – pretty much forever...
*
Plausibility aside, how would we know whether real science
was growing? (Useful new science, that is, as contrasted with the mere volume
of publications and other communications – which is simply a matter of words,
pictures and numbers.)
Who could evaluate whether change is real science not hype; and whether
increased amounts of self-styled scientific stuff (publications,
personnel, laboratories etc.) actually corresponded to more and better real
science?
Why should the default assumption be that increased size of
science as a professional activity corresponds to increased knowledge?
*
When scientific growth is expected, and when society acts-upon the
expectation, we have an overwhelming assumption of growth in science, an
assumption that science is growing – but that assumption says nothing at all
about whether there really is growth.
Indeed, so strong is the assumption that science is progressing
that we have a situation where a critic of science is expected to prove the
negative - that science is not growing. This is remarkable – instead of
scientists and the funders of science having to prove that they are making
progress we have a situation where the progress is assumed (unless proven
otherwise).
We have a situation where every scientific publication (once it
has been published) is nowadays presumed to be valid (unless proven otherwise).
This was not always the case! – to put it mildly.
*
One reason people assume an increase of knowledge is that modern
science has been ‘peer reviewed’ before publication – that is to say a
virtual-committee of other scientists have – if not exactly approved it, then
at least not vetoed its publication, based on their opinions of its quality.
However, what the opinion of a bunch of self-styled scientists has
to do with validity is never explained – since real science was supposed
to be about something more than opinion; indeed being about more than mere
opinion was precisely what supposedly made science science!
Yet since we are in a situation when, apparently, published science
is assumed to be valid (until proven otherwise), and in a situation when
publication depends on an opinion poll (i.e. peer review) – then ‘science’ of
this kind is no more valid than any other opinion poll.
*
The situation is that a bunch of senior researchers in each
research specialty (the peer review cartel) are assuring the outside-world that
yes – research volume is in fact the same as knowledge volume. And since
research volume is a product of research input, the conclusion is obvious: give
us more money!
*
When people assume real science is growing, and when they think they
perceive from output volume that real science is growing, this creates vast
possibilities for dishonesty, hype and spin.
Because people are expecting science to grow, and expecting there
to be regular breakthroughs, they tend to believe it when regular
breakthroughs are claimed (whether or not breakthroughs have actually
happened).
Indeed, if the breakthroughs are not obvious – then breakthroughs
will be looked for until breakthroughs are ‘found’.
(The same happens with genius – if there are no modern geniuses to
compare with the scores of geniuses observable 100 years ago – then this is
assumed to mean that we need to look harder for the geniuses which we just know
must be there...)
*
But how if there is really no growth in scientific knowledge – but
merely growth in scientific communications?
How if there is actual decline in real scientific knowledge
– how would we know this from outputs?
We wouldn’t. We would only know it from
declining capability. And declining capability, as argued above, we do
seem to observe.
Doing real science is hard
A thought experiment: Let us suppose that doing real science is
actually much harder than most people currently assume; much slower,
more difficult and less predictable.
*
Suppose that most competent and hardworking real scientists
actually make no indispensable and distinctive contribution to real science
– none at all - but merely incremental improvements, minor checks or refinements
in methods, the precision of measurements and the expression of theories.
And if they personally had not done it, it would have
slightly-slowed but would not have prevented progress: or somebody else would
have done it.
And that it is simply the nature of real science that
unpredictability, riskiness, is intrinsic. That there are no guarantees
that even able and hardworking scientists will actually achieve anything at
all.
Indeed suppose that the likeliest outcome is that most scientists
– most real scientists - will turn-out to have been redundant,
superfluous, and unnecessary – yet this outcome can be known only in
retrospect. We cannot predict who will succeed and who will fail.
And of course all this is not a thought experiment – it is
a simple statement of fact: real science is really hard.
(Ask any real scientist.)
*
Since real science is really hard, then this fact is incompatible
with the professionalization of science – with the idea of scientific research
as a career.
Since real science is irregular and infrequent and unpredictable,
then science could only be done in an amateur way; maybe as a sideline
from some other profession like teaching, practicing medicine, being a priest,
or as a hobby for the wealthy – or supported by a patron.
Professional science would then be regarded as an activity intrinsically
phoney; and the phoniness would increase as professionalization of science
increased and became more precisely measured, and as the profession of science
expanded – until it reached a situation where the visible products and evidence
of science (publications, personnel, buildings, organizations and their
funding) – the stuff bore zero relationship to the reality of science.
Professional scientists would produce stuff (like scientific
publications) regularly and frequently, but this stuff would actually have
nothing to do with real science.
Nothing to do with real
science.
*
Or, more exactly, the growing amount of stuff produced by the
growing numbers of professional science careerists, whose use of hype would
also be growing – the amount of this stuff would be so much greater
than the amount of real science, that any real science would be obscured
utterly.
*
This is precisely what we have.
The observation of growth in scientific knowledge became an
expectation of growth in science and finally an assumption of growth in
science.
And when it was being assumed that science was growing, the amount
of real science did not really need to grow, because the assumption that
it was growing framed the reality.
*
But if real science is as hard (slow, unpredictable,
uneven) as was always believed (until the mid 20th century); then
scientific progress cannot be taken for granted, cannot be expected or assumed.
Yet our society depends on scientific progress – if or when
scientific progress stops, our society will soon collapse, because it will not
grow – and our society depends on growth.
Despite, or maybe because, science is vital to our survival as a
civilization, so great is our societal arrogance that we do not regard science
as something real.
Instead we have made scientific progress a
matter of casual assumption, not of serious observation; hence scientific
progress has become the subject of unbounded wishful thinking and deceitful
propaganda.
When the bubble bursts
Real science is a way of getting at certain kinds of truth, but
the way that science works is absolutely dependent on honesty and integrity.
Our societal arrogance is such that we believe that we can have the advantages
of real science but at the same time subvert the honesty and integrity
of science whenever that happens to be expedient.
We act as if real science can necessarily be formalised,
mechanised and made a process of mass production. And we don’t even attempt to
check whether this is true.
Our societal arrogance is that we are in control of this
dishonesty – that the amount of hype and spin we apply to science is under our
control, trivial in its effect, and can be undone at will; that we can separate
the signal of honest real science from the noise of mass produced ‘research’-
and ‘back-calculate’ or reverse-engineer the truth of science from the lies and
exaggerations of careerist research...
*
But in fact we have no idea of the real situation in
science, no idea of the quantity or identity of valid knowledge, except that in
a system tending towards entropy (bias, selectivity, inaccuracy) we must assume
that the noise will tend to grow and swamp the signal.
Science has appeared to be growing, but the only sure and
dependable reality is increasing hype, spin and dishonesty.
The link between scientific stuff and scientific substance has
disappeared.
*
In sum: when the signals of science (‘publications’ or other
research communications including spoken words) lose their meaning, when the
meaning of science is detached from underlying reality, then there is no
limit to the mismatch.
Not knowing the truth, the mismatch between truth and un-truth
becomes un-measurable – there may be zero correlation between communications
and reality.
Scientific communications and underlying reality can be two
separate and independent domains. Which explains how real science is collapsing
while professional research outputs are booming.
*
The amount of real science (intermittent, infrequent,
unpredictable) has surely not stayed absolutely constant throughout this
inflationary process - but will surely have declined due to the
environment for real science becoming increasingly hostile.
So, what we call ‘science’ is an inflating bubble, just skin on
gas, and inflating bubbles eventually burst.
And the longer delayed the burst, the bigger the bubble will
become (the more gas, the less substance), and the bigger will be the
explosion.
*
When the scientific bubble bursts, what will be left over after
the explosion?
Maybe only old science will prove valid – science from an
era when most scientists believed in objective reality and that it was their
vocation to discover it; when most scientists were honest and trying to speak
the truth – as they understood it - about the natural world.
And from an era when, if scientists had nothing to say for a few
years then they said nothing for a few years; when, indeed, if scientists
discovered little or nothing then these scientists would state candidly that
they had discovered little or nothing.
How far would we need to go back? About two generations or fifty
years I should say – to before the mid nineteen sixties, and maybe more...
*
But, in an era of micro-specialization, will
there be anyone who can even understand old/ real science, leave aside the
problem of finding anyone who can actually do real science in the old
way?
Scientific validity is about coherence not
testing
The problem with science is a problem of validity. Real science
had robust (although not infallible) ways of establishing validity; modern professional
research cannot establish validity, because it does not recognise any
transcendent reality beyond the opinion of ‘scientists’.
To be more exact, modern professional research has methods
which are regarded as intrinsically providing validation – but the methods are
themselves unvalidated – indeed the methods used to assert validity are no more
than arbitrary conventions enforced by power.
*
Until recently, I usually described real science as being mostly a
matter of devising theories which had implications, and testing these
implications by observation or experiment.
In other words, science was supposedly about making and testing
predictions, devising theories and doing observations and experiments to test
them.
This ‘classic’ view of science is often described as Popperian,
being (broadly) based on the work of philosopher Karl Popper – for example in
the title of one of his books: Conjectures and refutations.
*
Of course there is more which needs to be said to give a
sufficient account of Popper’s ideas: the predictions must derive from theory, and
predictions should be sufficiently complex or non-obvious or counter-intuitive,
so as to be unlikely to happen by random chance. And so on.
But it is now clear that this sequence doesn’t happen much
nowadays, if it ever did.
And, indeed, that there are serious weaknesses about the
conceptualization of science as mostly a matter of testing predictions – since
this process turns out to be circular – once validation is merely a matter of
peer review, of consensus.
*
The main problem is that when science becomes big, as it is
now, the social processes of science come to control all aspects of science,
including defining what counts as a test of a prediction and what
counts as passing that test.
Testing now boils-down to the social processes of science, merely.
This means peer review = a poll of opinions = government by
committees (some actual committees, meeting in a room; some merely virtual
committees with participants distributed across time and space). Therefore the
validation process is made consensual, and disconnected from any notion of
testing putative knowledge in relation to reality.
*
Yet, the problem is therefore not so much at the level of testing
– but is at root a problem of coherence,
There can be no ‘testing’ without coherence. Without coherence
there is, indeed, nothing to test.
*
Incoherent theories do not have tightly-defined implications and
cannot make precise predictions, therefore there is no conceivable way in which
they could be put to a test.
So... incoherent theories cannot be tested, and most
theories in modern research are incoherent (in so far as they are even
articulated – there are branches of science operating under the delusion that
they do not have any theory), and modern careerist pseudo-science is powerfully
resistant to any attempt to create coherence.
When theories are incoherent, hence un-testable, therefore false
science can never be refuted. The process of (supposedly) ‘testing’ is
one that never ends; nothing can ever be put to a conclusive test, therefore
nothing is ever conclusively refuted.
Incoherent ‘science’ is not even false.
Therefore incoherent science can be kept going ad infinitum – whether it
is true or not. From a careerist perspective, therefore, the incoherence of
science may be a feature, not a bug.
Science as a sub-species of philosophy
Science is a child of philosophy, and as in philosophy, the basic
‘test’ of science is coherence.
Statements in science ought to cohere with other statements in
science, and this ought to be checked.
Testing ‘predictions’ by observation and experiment is merely
one type of checking for coherence. ‘Testing’ is, in fact, merely checking for
coherence between the predictions of a coherent theory and observations.
This process need not involve a temporal sequence, there no need
for prediction to precede the observation testing that prediction, since
‘predictions’ are (properly) not to do with time but with logic.
Testing in science ought not, therefore, to focus on predictions
such as ‘I predict now that x will happen under y circumstances in the future’
– but instead the focus should be – much more simply – on checking that the
various statements of science cohere in a logical fashion.
*
To put it another way: It is an axiom that all true scientific
statements are consistent with all other true scientific statements.
True statements should not contradict one another, they should
cohere.
In order that coherence not be vacuous, statements must be
sufficiently precise in their implications (implications being another word for
‘predictions’).
So that when it is discovered that there is no logical coherence
between two scientific propositions (two theories, 'facts' or whatever), and
assuming the reasoning process is sound, then one or both propositions
must be wrong.
*
Real scientific work is the process of making and learning about
propositions.
A newly made proposition that is not coherent with a bunch of
previously existing propositions may nonetheless be true, because all or some
of the previously existing propositions may be false.
Indeed that is one meaning of a scientific revolution – a
revolution is what happens when a new proposition succeeds in overturning a
bunch of old coherent propositions, and establishing a new network of coherent
propositions: a different set of propositions, coherent on a different basis.
This is always a work in progress, and at any moment there is
considerable incoherence in science which is being sorted-out – or, at least,
that is the usual assumption.
*
The fatal flaw in modern science is that there is no such
sorting-out.
Incoherence is ignored, propositions are merely piled loosely
together and the result is called a theory.
Or the revelation of incoherence is eluded,
rather than sorted-out, by the process of micro-specialization and the creation
of isolated little worlds within-which there may be coherence, but between-which
there is zero coherence (and no attempt to check or impose coherence).
No such thing as ‘Science’ anymore
Using this very basic requirement of coherence, it is obvious that
much of modern science is not science because it is incoherent – its theories
do not make sense, or are obviously wrong.
And furthermore there no coherence between the specialties of
research – specialties are not checked against each other. Indeed such checks
between specialties are often regarded as impossible – on the basis that
different scientific specialties are seen as incommensurable (i.e. not
measurable against a common standard).
It is not that the propositions of modern professional research
are checked and fail the checks, but that no attempt whatsoever is made
to check for coherence between specialities. Insofar as any need for coherence
between micro-specialisms is acknowledged, the actual business of checking is
endlessly deferred...
Indeed, some philosophies of science have evolved to rationalize
the endless deferral of checking for cohesion between specialisms; and there is
a big literature in the philosophy of science which purports to prove that
different types of science are incommensurable, incomparable, and independent –
hence cannot meaningfully be checked against one another.
This implies that there is no unit of scientific
validity greater than the micro-specialty. This implies that each
micro-specialty (with its narrow selection of foundational assumptions and
methods stands alone. This implies that there is no such thing as ‘Science’
and that the individual scientific specialty is the largest possible unit of
coherence.
*
If this is true, and it is true in the sense that nobody has even tried
to demonstrate coherence across and between the ‘scientific’ research
specialities - then science as a whole does not add-up.
In other words, there are only the hundreds of microspecialist
‘sciences’ that cast no light on one another, are irrelevant to each other, do
not constrain each other.
This means in turn that all the different micro-specialties that
now constitute ‘science’ would not be contributing to anything greater than
themselves considered individually.
This means that, formally speaking, there is no such thing as
Science only hundreds of ‘sciences’– ‘Science’ is merely an arbitrary
collection, a loose heap of micro-specialties each yielding autonomous
micro-knowledge of unknowable applicability, and the whole given the honorific
title of ‘Science’.
*
This is very obviously true of modern medical science and biology. For example the
massive specialism of ‘neuroscience’ does not add-up to anything like
‘understanding’ of the brain or nervous system – it is merely a collection of
hundreds of autonomous micro-specialties and factoids about nervous tissue.
Observations of this, then of that, then of something else – pile ‘em high and
call it neuroscience!
These micro-specialties were not checked for consistency
with each other at any point, and as a consequence they are not
consistent with each other. Neuroscience was not conducted with an aim
of creating a coherent body of knowledge, and as a result it is not a
coherent body of knowledge.
‘Neuroscience’, as a term (it is not a concept, does not rise anywhere close
to being a concept) is merely an excuse for funding a vast heap of mutual
irrelevance.
*
It is not a matter of whether the micro-specialties in modern
science are correct observations (in the past they probably were honest,
nowadays they are quite likely to be dishonest). But that isolated observations
– even if honest - are worthless.
Isolated specialties composed of isolated observation are
worthless.
Raking-together heaps of worthless observations makes – a
worthless heap of observations.
*
It is only when observations and specialties are linked with others (using theories)
that consistency can even potentially be checked, whether or not it actually is
checked; only then that understanding might arise - and then
‘predictions’ can potentially emerge.
Checking science for its coherence includes testing predictions,
and maximizes both the usefulness and testability of science; but a science
based purely on testing predictions (and ignoring coherence) will become both
incoherent and trivial.
Real science is first coherent, then its coherence is deliberately
checked – sometimes (not always) by testing.
But modern research is incoherent, and therefore whatever
masquerades as checking and testing is not merely irrelevant but actively
misleading – merely an excuse for unending funding of permanently inconclusive
research.
Doing science because science is fun?
Committed scientists in recent decades have often justified
themselves in the face of increasing careerism, fragmentation, incoherence and
dishonesty by emphasizing that doing-science (being ‘a scientist’) is enormous fun
– and that this is their main motivation for doing it.
*
Although understandable, this is a foolish and indeed desperate
line of defence. Many things are 'fun' for the people who happen to like them,
but fun or not-fun, science was supposed to be about reality.
And Hitler, Stalin and Mao seemingly enjoyed being dictators, and redefining
‘truth’ for their own purposes by the exercise of their power to do so. Perhaps
they found all this ‘fun’ – but does that justify them? Maybe torturers find their
work fun?
Crosswords, reading romantic novels, getting-drunk, chatting with
friends – all these may be fun, may indeed be a lot more fun (or, at least,
easier fun) than science; but does that justify making them into lifelong
careers and spending trillions of dollars on their support and subsidy?
That it may be fun does not justify science.
*
Plus of course science is not fun anymore: because being a
minor bureaucrat and filling-in forms with lies is not fun (or if it is, the
fun is not science); planning your work in detail for the next three years then
rigidly sticking to the plan is not fun; being forbidden to do what interests
you but forced to do what is funded is not fun; spending your time discussing
grants instead of ideas is not fun...
Real science done for
vocational reasons is (or can be) fun (more exactly, it is profoundly
satisfying); but pursuing a modern research career is not science and is not
fun.
A modern research career may be rewarding in terms of money,
power, status, lifestyle and the like, or sustained by the hope of these – but
is not something done for its intrinsic fun-ness.
*
Of course the ‘science is fun’ line of argument is mostly trying to avoid the
‘science is useful’ trap.
The usefulness trap must be avoided because the application of
science is something intrinsically unknowable. Science is about discovering
reality – and knowing this may or may not be useful, may be beneficial or it
might well turn out to be harmful – indeed fatal; so usefulness cannot
be guaranteed.
*
At least usefulness cannot be guaranteed if you are
being honest – although modern researchers seldom are honest, hence they
often do claim that science is predictable, useful and intrinsically
beneficial.
(Indeed, in the UK, all government and government-tainted sources of
funding require that a successful applicant must make the case that their
research is indeed useful and intrinsically beneficial. In other words, the
applicant for these sources of money must lie in order to be
successful. All recipients of such resources are demonstrable liars.)
Modern researchers also sometimes pretend that their kind of
science is ‘fun’ – yet what they are doing is not science, and what they are
getting ‘fun’ from is other stuff entirely: such as the business of trying to
get famous, powerful, rich – enjoying the lifestyle of conferences, gossip and
intrigue...
*
So real vocational science is ‘fun’ in the sense of personally
rewarding, but this does not justify real science; and almost all of what
currently gets called science is neither real nor fun.
After science
The classic science fiction novel A canticle for Liebowitz
by Walter M Miller portrays a post-nuclear-holocaust world in which the
tradition of scientific practice – previously handed-down from one generation
of scientists to the next – has been broken. Only a few scientific artefacts
remain, such as fragments of electronic equipment.
It turns out that ‘after science’, scientific objects and records
make no sense and are wildly misinterpreted. A blueprint is regarded as if it
was an illuminated manuscript, diodes are regarded as lucky talismans.
Modern ‘science’ has entered a similar state in which the artefacts of science
remain – such as places called universities, the academic hierarchy, white
coats, laboratory organization, expensive tools and machines, statistical
methods, and the peer review mechanism – but understanding of what these mean
has been lost.
*
A theme associated with philosophers such as the Michaels Polanyi
and Oakeshott is that explicit knowledge – such as is found in textbooks and
scientific articles – is only a selective summary that omits that the most
important capability derives from implicit, traditional or ‘tacit’
knowledge.
It is this un-articulated knowledge – embedded in traditions,
habits, practices - that leads to genuine human understanding of the natural
world, accurate prediction and the capacity to make effective interventions.
Tacit knowledge is handed-on between- and across-generations by slow,
assimilative processes which require extended, relatively unstructured and only
semi-purposive human contact.
What is being transmitted and inculcated is an over-arching
purpose, a style of thought, a learned but then spontaneous framing of reality,
a sense of how problems should be tackled, and a gut-feeling for evaluating the
work or oneself, as well as others.
This kind of process was in the past achieved by such means as
familial vocations, prolonged apprenticeship, co-residence, and extended time
spent in association with a Master – and by the fact that the Master and
apprentice personally selected each other.
The Master-apprentice pattern was seen in all areas of life where
independence, skill and depth of knowledge were expected: crafts, arts, music,
scholarship – and science.
*
Although such methods sound a bit mysterious, not to say
obscurationist, to modern ears – in fact they are solid realism and common
sense.
Such methods for ensuring the transmission of subtle knowledge
recognize the gulf between on the one hand being able to do something,
and on the other hand knowing how you have done it; and the further gap
between knowing how you have done something, and being able to teach it by
explicit and free-standing instructions.
Such systems as apprenticeship recognize that the most important
aspects of knowledge may be those which are not known or understood to be the
most important, or may even be in opposition to that which is believed or
supposed to be important.
Many things can (tacitly) be learned that cannot
(explicitly) be taught.
*
The educational ‘method’ was that an apprentice should spend a lot
of time with the Master in many situations; and as for educational evaluation,
the best way for a Master to know that his skill really has been passed-on, is
for him to spend a lot of time with the apprentice in many situations.
Imperfect as it inevitably was, inefficient as it seems;
nonetheless traditions were as a matter of observable fact maintained
and often improved over centuries by means of apprenticeship – which was
regarded as the safest and surest way of ensuring that the knowledge and skills
could be sustained and developed.
However, modern priorities are different. The preservation and
development of high-level human skills and expertise is no longer regarded as a
priority, something to which many other concerns will inevitably need to be
subordinated.
And the ‘Master–apprentice’ model of education - which works,
and which stretches back in human history as far as we know - has been all-but
discarded from science (and much of mainstream culture) over recent decades.
*
Indeed the assumptions have now been reversed.
The discarding of traditions of apprenticeship and prolonged human
contact in science was not due to any new discovery that apprenticeship was –
after all – unnecessary, let alone that the new bureaucratic systems of
free-standing explicit aims and objectives, instructions, summaries and lists
of core knowledge and competencies, tick-boxes and numerical rating etc. were superior
to apprenticeship.
Yet there is nothing to suggest that these bureaucratic processes
are remotely the equal of apprenticeship: indeed there is nothing to suggest
that they work at all.
Rather, the Master–apprentice system has been discarded despite
the overwhelming evidence of its superiority; and has been replaced by the
growth of bureaucratic regulation.
*
The main reason for discarding apprenticeship is probably that
scientific manpower, personnel or ‘human resources’ (as they are now termed)
have expanded vastly and quickly over the past 60 years – probably about
ten-fold.
There was, indeed, zero possibility of such rapid and sustained
quantitative expansion being achieved using the labour-intensive apprenticeship
methods of the past.
The tradition of apprenticeship was therefore discarded because it
stood in the path of the expansion of scientific manpower. Stood, that is to
say, in the path of an expansion of the power of leading scientists –
who in this process evolved from being real scientists into professional
research managers.
The choice was between either maintaining the ethos and skills of
real science, or else going ahead with the rapid and large scale expansion of
research manpower.
The choice that was made was to discard the ethos and skills of
science.
*
It has now become implicitly accepted among the mass of
professional ‘scientists’ that the decisions which matter most in science are
those imposed upon science by outside forces: by employers (deciding who
gets the jobs, who gets the promotion), funders (deciding who gets the big
money), editors and publishers (deciding who gets their work published in the
big journals), bureaucratic regulators (deciding who gets allowed to do what
work), and the law courts (deciding whose ideas get backed-up, or criminalized,
by the courts) – and of course politicians (deciding the framework within which
all these others operate).
It is these bureaucratic mechanisms that constitute ‘real life’
and the ‘bottom line’ for modern research practice.
The tradition has been broken.
*
We are living After Science, in the same fashion and for
similar reasons that philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre recognized (in his 1981
book of that title) that we are living After Virtue.
Modern science is in that post-holocaust situation described in A
Canticle for Liebowitz – the transmission of tacit knowledge has been
broken; we have a simulacrum of science but not the reality.
The destruction of real science was concealed by
the escalation of hype and spin, thus science was gradually rebuilt as a
Potemkin Village: a superficially-impressive façade of pseudo-knowledge
concealing a morass of corrupt bureaucracy and mediocre careerism.
Real science in one sentence
If you are truthful, and spontaneously motivated to spend a lot of
time and effort thinking-about and investigating some thing, then
there is a reasonable chance, but no guarantee, that you will discover something.
Origins of this book
The origins of this book lie in my childhood idealisation of
science and its continuation as an ideal well into middle age – and the
inexorable dismantling of this ideal by accumulated experience.
What kind of experience?
At first it was noticing that scientists were seldom doing the
best work of which they were capable, and becoming aware of their reluctance to
take risks or be long-termist in pursuit of scientifically-ambitious work
(their preference for high and reliable outputs of mediocre and unimportant
work over the smaller chance of major work).
That was dismaying. But primarily it was the experience of
non-honesty (that is, indifference to honesty) that did for me; the
observation that non-honesty was rewarded in career terms.
And finally encountering the systematic imposition of non-honesty;
not only indirectly by rewarding hype, spin, fashionable incompetence
and lies; but eventually directly by the punishment of honesty.
*
Modern scientists are not merely expected to be routinely
dishonest when this is expedient (e.g. for career reasons, for the convenience
of professional colleagues, for personal and institutional funding etc.); but
scientists are now actually forbidden to be truthful all the time and about
everything.
Of course, the process is concealed by words, is reframed in
apparently more acceptable ways – but I invite anyone who doubts what I say
actively to try actively practicing science with scrupulous honesty
- honesty, that is, in all matters scientific: even in
applications for grants, jobs, promotions, tenure, the presentation of research
‘plans’, research assessment exercises, press releases and so on. Honest in
everything.
Any such individual will almost certainly be confronted with
serious problems and intense pressures within one month, probably much sooner.
*
This book is based on one person’s knowledge and experience, and
is thereby limited in many ways. For example, I do not travel much and have not
been to many conferences.
On the other hand, I have worked across an unusually wide range of
bioscience and medicine; and for seven and a half years I solo-edited (i.e. no
peer review) a large, monthly journal of ideas - international in scope and
with very broad-based bioscience content.
I have also known several outstanding real scientists (in the
physical sciences, as well as the biosciences and medicine), and some experts
in the conduct of real science.
Still, whatever may be their limitations, my knowledge and
experience are at any rate wide enough and deep enough to draw general
conclusions; especially when corruption in science is so very common and so
very obvious.
You don’t need to be much of a marksman to hit a barn door at five
paces...
Further reading and references
The fact that I have not referenced the text of this book comes
partly from idleness, partly from the desire to make the reading experience
more enjoyable; but mostly from my intention – or at least hope – of opening
eyes to the obvious, of clarifying the already-known - rather
than persuading by weight of (supposed) facts.
(If you need persuading, then you cannot be
persuaded.)
Evidence of the corruption of science, its endemic dishonesty, is
all around us and everywhere we look – we need merely to allow the scales to
fall from our eyes, need merely to remove our blinkers.
To pick-up and examine specific items of dishonesty is
merely to diminish the impact of the overwhelming whole by arbitrary, piecemeal
and detached consideration.
*
Nonetheless in the past I have tried to do exactly this – to
document the corruptions of modern ‘science’ with referenced papers.
So, for those who want ‘evidence’, here is a list of my previous
publications on themes covered by this book, some of them statistical and
historical, replete with a wide range of references to further literature.
All these publications have myself as single author except where
otherwise indicated:
· The cancer of bureaucracy: How it
will destroy science, medicine, education; and eventually everything else.
Medical Hypotheses. 2010; 74: 961-965.
· After science: Has the tradition
been broken? Medical Hypotheses. 2010; 74: 623-625.
· Hunter RS, Oswald AJ, Charlton
BG. The elite brain drain. Economic Journal. 2009; 119: F231-F251.
· Why are modern scientists so dull?
How science selects for perseverance and sociability at the expense of
intelligence and creativity. Medical Hypotheses. 2009; 72:
237-43.
· The vital role of transcendental
truth in science. Medical Hypotheses. 2009; 72:
373-376.
· Sex ratios in the most-selective
elite US undergraduate colleges and universities. Medical
Hypotheses. 2009; 73: 127-129.
· Are you an honest scientist?
Truthfulness in science should be an iron law, not a vague aspiration.
Medical Hypotheses. 2009; 73: 633-635.
· Are you an honest academic?
Eight questions about truth. Oxford Magazine. 2009; 287: 8-10.
· The zombie science of
evidence-based medicine: a personal retrospective. Journal of Evaluation in
Clinical Practice. 2009; 15: 930-934.
· Clever sillies: Why high IQ people
tend to be deficient in common sense. Medical Hypotheses.
2009; 73: 867-870.
· Pioneering studies of IQ
by G.H. Thomson and J.F. Duff - An example of established knowledge
subsequently 'hidden in plain sight' Medical Hypotheses 2008; 71:
625-628.
· Figureheads,
ghost-writers and pseudonymous quant bloggers: The recent evolution of
authorship in science publishing. Medical Hypotheses 2008; 71: 475-480.
· Zombie science: A
sinister consequence of evaluating scientific theories purely on the basis of
enlightened self-interest. Medical Hypotheses 2008; 71: 327-329.
· First a hero of science and
now a martyr to science: The James Watson Affair - Political correctness
crushes free scientific communication. Medical Hypotheses 2008; 70:
1077-1080.
· Charlton BG, Andras P.
'Down-shifting' among top UK scientists? - The decline of 'revolutionary
science' and the rise of 'normal science' in the UK compared with the USA. Medical
Hypotheses 2008; 70: 465-472.
· Crick's gossip test and
Watson's boredom principle: A pseudo-mathematical analysis of effort in
scientific research Medical Hypotheses 2008: 70: 1-3.
· Charlton, BG, &
Andras P. Evaluating universities using simple scientometric research-output
metrics: Total citation counts per university for a retrospective seven-year
rolling sample. Science and Public Policy. 2007; 34: 555-563.
· Peer usage versus peer
review. BMJ. 2007; 335: 451.
· Measuring revolutionary
biomedical science 1992-2006 using Nobel prizes, Lasker (clinical medicine)
awards and Gairdner awards (NLG metric). Medical Hypotheses. 2007;
69:1-5.
· Which are the best
nations and institutions for revolutionary science 1987-2006? analysis using a
combined metric of Nobel prizes, Fields medals, Lasker awards and Turing awards
(NFLT metric). Medical Hypotheses. 2007; 68: 1191-1194.
· Scientometric
identification of elite 'revolutionary science' research institutions by
analysis of trends in Nobel prizes 1947-2006. Medical Hypotheses. 2007;
68: 931-934.
· Boom or bubble? Is
medical research thriving or about to crash? Medical Hypotheses. 2006;
66: 1-2.
· Charlton B Andras P.
Oxford University's Research Output in the UK context – Thirty-year analysis of
publications and citations. Oxford Magazine 2006; 254: 19-20.
· Charlton B Andras P. Oxbridge
versus the ‘Ivy League’: 30 year citation trends. Oxford Magazine 2006:
255: 16-17.
· Charlton B Andras P.
Best in the arts, catching-up in science – what is the best future for Oxford? Oxford
Magazine 2006; 256: 25-6.
· Charlton BG, Andras P.
The future of 'pure' medical science: the need for a new specialist
professional research system. Medical Hypotheses. 2005; 65: 419-25.
· Charlton BG, Andras P. Medical
research funding may have over-expanded and be due for collapse. Quarterly
Journal of Medicine. 2005; 98: 53-5.
Selected sources and acknowledgments
Bronowski, Jacob (1908-1974)
Jacob Bronowski came to my attention when I was fourteen years old,
with his stunningly brilliant and heartfelt 1973 television documentary series The
Ascent of Man. This built-upon a vague childhood interest in science to
‘convert’ me to ‘humanism’ – the religion of science as the engine and essence
of human progress. Afterwards I read and re-read pretty much everything
Bronowski ever wrote, but especially The Common Sense of Science (1951)
and Science and Human Values (1956). I would now regard Bronowski as an
(intrinsically un-replicable) transitional figure between science based
in orthodox religiousness and careerist research derived from modern nihilism.
Bronowski was raised a Jew and later became a militant atheist – but always
retaining his inculcated religious devotion to transcendental values
(especially truth but also beauty). Despite later divergences, I retain from
Bronowski the critical insight that science depends utterly on ‘the habit of
truth’ – that truthfulness is non-optional, an iron law.
Calne, Roy Yorke
From conversation and reading his autobiography The Ultimate
Gift, the great scientist and heroic surgical pioneer Roy Calne made me
recognize how rapidly and radically medical research had changed and become
corrupted during the decades of his career.
Crick, Francis (1916-2004)
Although I was aware of him from my mid-teens, it was after 1994
when I embarked on a career change as a theoretical scientist, that I regarded
Francis Crick as a spiritual mentor and model. I was particularly influenced by
his autobiography What mad pursuit (1988).
Gregory Clark
Economic historian, University of California at Davis. Very few
books have had such impact on my thinking as A farewell to alms: a brief
economic history of the world. I didn’t really believe that there was
anyone alive capable of such large scale thinking; and I later had the good
fortune to meet Clark and have several in-depth discussions.
Einstein, Albert (1879-1955)
Naturally, Einstein always had for me god-like status as the
pinnacle of modern scientific achievement and living – and I have read
innumerable biographies and memoirs – however it all began with an
autobiographical essay in a multi-author volume called I believe: the
personal philosophies of twenty-three eminent men and women of our time
(1940) that I found on our bookshelves at home, in a wartime edition.
Feynman, Richard (1918-1988)
Feynman was a later influence on me – probably from around 1988;
as a representative of uncompromising, fearless honesty and scientific
integrity yet without (apparently) any trace of transcendental belief. Like
Einstein, Feynman was raised as a Jew but became very much a modern ‘liberated’
man. Yet, it is not possible consistently to use Feynman as a mentor, since his
personal decision to be utterly truthful had no deeper rationale, and has no
traction in the corruptly dishonest world of modern research. Feynman got away
with truthfulness for a long time, due to his personal charm, terrifying
brilliance and Nobel Prize – but I now see him as one of the last of a
transitional generation of religious converts to non-nihilistic atheism, after
which careerism and full-nihilism took-over completely.
Hannam, James
A popular book by Hannam called God’s philosophers (2010) –
although not a great book – effectively hammered-home for me the substantial
and undeniable achievements of medieval science – that is, of science before
there was such a thing as ‘science’.
Healy, David
Since I read his Suspended Revolution (1991) I have avidly
been reading the work of David Healy, and his books on the history, sociology
and practice of psychiatry, psychopharmacology and medicine generally –
including his detailed and conclusive documentation of the thorough corruption
of research and practice especially since the mid-1960s. In my estimation,
Healy is incomparably the greatest writer on these topics in the English
language, and it has been a privilege to know him as a friend and (in a small
way) as a collaborator.
Hesse, Herman (1877-1962)
Hesse was author of The Glass Bead Game (1943) also known
as Magister Ludi and Das Glasperlenspiel. This is a
memorable account of the fascination of formal intellectual activity for its
own sake, as an utterly absorbing ‘game’ – cut-off from the real world, from
usefulness, from practical applications.
Horrobin, David L (1939-2003)
David Horrobin founded Medical Hypotheses on Popperian
principles, and bequeathed the journal’s editorship to me. He was one of the
last classic scientists to succeed in medical research – and in order to do so
he needed to leave the conventional academic structure and self-fund via his
business activities in pharmacology (and also become the object of
extraordinary resentment). Horrobin was the first to notice and document that
the rate of clinical innovation had declined since the mid 1960s - Horrobin,
D.F. Scientific medicine - success or failure? In: Weatherall, D.J.; Ledingham,
J.G.G.; Warrell, D.A. (Eds.) Oxford Textbook of Medicine, 2nd Edn.
Oxford University Press, Oxford. 1987: 2.1-2.3.
Hull, David L. (1935-2010)
Hull’s great work Science as a process (1988) ingeniously
uses the theory of evolution as its example of how science can be
conceptualized as a process of evolution by natural selection – with science
regarded in terms of the replication of theories and professional status as the
main evaluation. Hull’s empirically-dense account seems true of classic or
‘real’ science – and he therefore assumed that scientific status was constrained
by reality. However since Hull’s explanatory model has no reference to
transcendental truth (real reality) as a regulatory ideal; the evolutionary
concept of science turns-out to be equally true of generic professional
research of all types – including ‘zombie’ science. I knew Hull somewhat,
having met and corresponded with him – and he was on the Medical Hypotheses
editorial board; and my impression was that in late life he recognized with
considerable dismay that science had (since the period described in his main
book) undergone a ‘turn’ and evolved away from a concern with the real world
and into autonomous careerism.
Michael Mabe, Mayur Amin.
Growth dynamics of scholarly and scientific journals.
Scientimetrics. 2001; 51: 147-162.
Oakeshott, Michael (1901-1990)
Rationalism in Politics, 1962.
Polanyi, Michael (1891-1976)
Personal Knowledge, 1958.
Popper, Karl (1902-1994)
I came across the work of Popper in my late teens via the book of
that title by Bryan Magee (1973) – I went on to read some of Popper’s own work,
and particularly liked his autobiography Unended Quest (1977 edition).
Popper’s normative description has been vastly influential in British science,
and it is still used to tell undergraduates how to structure their
investigations. It was also the major influence on the founding by David L
Horrobin of Medical Hypotheses, the theoretical journal I edited
from 2003-2010 – Popper had indeed been a member of the editorial advisory
board from about 1974 until his death. Yet, for all the lip service paid to
Popper, it is clear that his ideas have zero real influence on modern
mainstream science; probably because Popper, like most other philosophers of
science, tried to describe science purely in terms of its process and pragmatic
value to the happiness and comfort of society; and without regard to its
transcendental aims.
Rees, Jonathan
Professor of Dermatology, University of Edinburgh – previously at
Newcastle University. For many years, at varying intervals, I have met and
talked with Jonathan about science and medicine in broad and specific terms.
Despite considerable professional success, he has - so far as I can tell -
remained completely honest.
Romer, Paul
I got the (mistaken) perspective of ‘economic growth fuelling
science fuelling economic growth’ from an audio interview with Romer on
econtalk.org dated 27 August 2007. Indeed, I had co-argued something similar
myself (with Peter Andras) in a book called The Modernization Imperative
(2003).
Watson, James D
I read Watson’s The Double Helix about 1975-ish and have
re-read it many times since; and also enjoyed numerous other accounts of the
discovery of the structure of DNA – especially the 1987 TV movie Life Story.
Also influential more recently was the essay: J. Watson, Succeeding in science:
some rules of thumb, Science 1993; 261: 1812.
Ziman, John (1925-2005)
Ziman’s early books such as Public Knowledge (1968) and Reliable
Knowledge (1978) were historical and sociological descriptions of classic
science of the golden age; but Ziman really distinguished himself by being (so
far as I know) the first thoroughly to document the death of classic science in
Real Science, published in 2000. Here he described the transformation of
‘academic’ science into ‘post-academic’ science. In this book I have re-named
Ziman’s academic science as ‘real’ science and his ‘post-academic’ science as
‘professional research’. I knew Ziman slightly when he was on the editorial board
of Medical Hypotheses, and am pleased to dedicate this book to his
memory.
Biographical note
Bruce G Charlton is Visiting Professor of Theoretical Medicine at
the University of Buckingham and Reader in Evolutionary Psychiatry at Newcastle
University. Bruce has an unusually broad intellectual experience: he graduated
with honours from the Newcastle Medical School, took a doctorate at the Medical
Research Council Neuroendocrinology group, and did postgraduate training in
psychiatry and public health. He has held university lectureships in
physiology, anatomy, epidemiology, and psychology; and has a Masters degree in
English Literature from Durham. From 2003-10 Professor Charlton solo-edited Medical
Hypotheses; a monthly international journal that published frequently
speculative, sometimes amusing, and often controversial ideas and theories
across the whole of medicine and beyond. He has published considerably more
than two hundred scientific papers and academic essays in these fields, and
contributed journalism to UK national broadsheets and weekly magazines. Bruce G
Charlton is author of Thought Prison: the fundamental nature of political
correctness (University of Buckingham Press, 2011).
Subscribe to: Posts (Atom)